URL: http://www.nature.com/cgi-taf/DynaPage.taf?file=/nature/journal/v408/n6810/full/408275a0_fs.html
Date accessed: 31 January 2001
Nature 408, 275 (2000) © Macmillan Publishers Ltd.
16 November 2000
A report from a
European ethics committee gives a valuable summary of the issues surrounding
stem-cell research. Debates over therapeutic cloning should not distract
attention from central ethical concerns and alternative stem-cell techniques.
On the trail of the latest Holy Grail, researchers can sometimes lose sight
of the wider issues and of alternative avenues. Scientists lobbying passionately
for research on human embryonic stem cells, and in particular on 'therapeutic
cloning', should pay heed. Cold water is thrown on therapeutic cloning this week
by a report from a group of 12 wise men and women, convened to advise the
European Union (EU) on bioethics (see page
277). It concludes that the creation of embryos by somatic-cell nuclear
transfer for research on stem-cell therapy would be "premature".
Analysis of the legitimacy of that assertion could itself fill pages, and it is
this aspect that will no doubt claim public attention, dealing as it does with
the explosive cocktail of human cloning and embryo research. Therapeutic cloning has potential advantages. In this technique, somatic
nuclei from a patient's body — nuclei from non-reproductive cells — are
fused with donated eggs (oocytes). Embryos are thereby produced from which
pluripotent stem cells — those able to differentiate into any body-cell type,
and genetically identical to the patient — could be generated. Cells or
tissues derived from such embryonic stem cells for transplantation would not be
rejected by the patient's body. The question of whether therapeutic cloning
should be allowed is currently generating much heat in Britain, and elsewhere.
But that is only one part of the vast field of regenerative medicine being
opened up by stem cells. There is a danger that the issue of therapeutic cloning
will distract politicians and the public from the wider issues and opportunities
offered by embryonic stem cells for both therapeutics and basic cell biology. The real interest of the report is in disentangling the broader range of
issues. Britain is already at the far end of the moral spectrum, being one of
the few countries in the world to authorize the 'utilitarian' deliberate
creation of embryos for research, a practice that runs against the European
Convention on Human Rights and Biomedicine. In most of Europe, and elsewhere,
the fundamental question is not whether the cloning of human embryos to produce
stem cells should be allowed, but whether the collection of stem cells from
human embryos should be allowed at all. And it is here, in the exploration of
the use of basic embryonic stem cells, rather than in somatic nuclear transfer,
that the scientific promise is greatest. Promise But the ethical controversy over the use of human embryos as a supply of
embryonic stem cells has perhaps done science a favour. Three years ago, before
human embryonic stem cells had been cultured, xenotransplantation was being
pursued as the solution to cell and organ transplants (see Nature
391, 325; 1998). The breakthrough in 1998 in culturing human
embryonic stem cells has now radically shifted the focus of research. In turn,
whereas the use of such cells has since become the obvious way forward, the
controversy over the use of embryos is now encouraging research into
'alternative' sources that might otherwise have been ignored: adult stem cells. Use of adult cells Adult stem cells still appear of limited use because they cannot proliferate
indefinitely. But who says they are not capable of doing so? Differentiation is
a complex process, determined by the switching on and off of thousands of genes
and the production of millions of proteins. The intellectual appeal of human
embryonic stem cells, with their ability to divide indefinitely and potentially
generate all types of cells, should not be allowed to lead to a neglect of other
avenues of research, particularly given the ethical issues involved. A
case-by-case approach will probably be needed — in mice, the entire blood
system can now be regenerated from a single adult blood stem cell. A cynical view of a bioethics committee is that it simply puts a brake on the
introduction of new technologies until public acceptance is inevitably in place.
In the EU report, ethical concerns are not only doing science a service by
providing a bridge to society's legitimate concern about issues such as the
rights of the human embryo, but they are also giving science an opportunity to
stand back and think of alternative approaches, rather than putting all of its
oocytes in one basket. In Europe, the starkly contrasting views on embryo research are similarly
having the beneficial effect of forcing the continent to debate and come to
terms with fundamental ethical and scientific questions. US politicians would
perhaps do well to take note of the debate in Europe. By comparison, the current
US legal situation — with moral restrictions in the public sector, and almost
anything allowed in the private sector — is both hypocritical and ethically
incoherent.
Although countries opposed in principle to embryo research, such as hard-line
Germany or Ireland, are unlikely to waver, the huge therapeutic promise of
embryonic stem cells is likely to lead to changes in the law in countries such
as France. There, a ban on human embryo research is likely to be lifted to allow
embryonic stem cells to be collected, but only from the 35,000 frozen surplus
embryos left over from attempts at in vitro fertilization. One need not
be a Jesuit theologian to realize that the ethical argument for this is
overwhelming: if such embryos are to be destroyed anyway, why not use them to
relieve suffering? Obtaining consensus on whether human embryo research should
be allowed is impossible, given the diversity of views. The EU report is
therefore wise to leave this question up to national legislatures, rather than
seeking to impose Europe-wide rules on EU research funding.
Stem cells from adult tissues such as bone are currently of limited use in that
they do not grow as easily as embryonic stem cells, or differentiate into as
many cell types. But are adult stem cells irretrievably committed to
differentiating into a limited number of cell types? The past year has seen
reports of blood stem cells generating muscle tissue and muscle stem cells
generating blood cells. Even one year ago, few would have believed such feats
possible. Brain cells, once thought irreplaceable, can now be regenerated. Might
all types of brain cells be regenerated from an adult human stem cell? Why not?
Categories: 31. Stem Cells, 39. General Issues About Scientific Research