Real and metaphorical moral limits in the biotech debate
Date accessed: 9 October 2001
Commentary Marc A. Saner Marc A. Saner is managing director at the Ethics &
Policy Issues Centre (http://www.carleton.ca/epic/),
Department of Philosophy, Carleton University 1125 Colonel By Drive,
Ottawa ON K1S 5B6, Canada From the beginning, the regulatory and
public debate over biotechnology has been closely tied to the question of
whether it matters what process is used to develop a product. Generally
speaking, critics of genetic engineering argue that, yes, it does matter,
while proponents argue that, no, only the features of the product matter. I argue here that this question is at
the root of the ethical debate over modern biotechnology. I argue further
that fully understanding this question is of critical importance in moving
the ethical debate surrounding modern biotechnology ahead. The process-versus-product view is
important to the ethical analysis because the two views neatly map onto
the distinction between nonconsequentialist and consequentialist ethics.
Simply put, nonconsequentialists formulate ethical prescriptions that
stand regardless of the consequences, whereas consequentialists consider
consequences in ethical decision making. For example, a
nonconsequentialist may hold that killing an innocent human being is wrong
under all circumstances. In contrast, a consequentialist would not
prohibit such killing absolutely, but would attempt to judge it in the
context of predicted consequences (e.g., one can imagine a lifeboat
situation in which the choice is between a single act of murder and the
probable death of all passengers). The critical point is that
nonconsequentialists may formulate absolute moral limits, whereas
consequentialists will prefer to formulate ethical prescriptions
contingent on the forecasting of consequences. |
|
|
|
Within this classification, the process
view is nonconsequentialist and the product view is consequentialist.
Nonconsequentialists may argue that some or all types of genetic
engineering are wrong, because these methods lie beyond a moral limit. An
expression of this view would be, for example, "the genetic
engineering of humans violates the basic dignity that all humans
possess." In support of this line of argument, one can point out that
metaphysical concepts, such as "dignity" and the prescription of
moral limits, are common ingredients of existing and widely accepted legal
and moral frameworks; for example, in human rights declarations. The
categorical refusal to consider the use of human embryos as a source of
stem cells is based on such an approach. Arguing that some nonhuman
animals also have "dignity" that could be violated can extend
this line of argument. Finally, one may single out genetic engineering as
the worst offender within biological technologies, all of which may be
considered a threat to the "intrinsic value" of nature (the
existence of such value is implied in the United Nations World Charter for
Nature of 1982) or to the "integrity of ecological systems" (the
existence of such integrity is explicit in the new Earth Charter
Initiative, see http://www.earthcharter.org/draft/charter.htm).
I would call such moral arguments "the prescription of a 'real' moral
limit." In contrast, consequentialists would
argue that no method is intrinsically wrong, morally speaking. What really
matters is the harm that may result, and such harm should be forecasted
with risk assessment methodology. Very broad categories of goods may be
considered within this approach. As a result, risk assessment may have to
be conducted not just with human health and the economy in mind, but also
to assess environmental, aesthetic, social, and political change. Still,
what matters is the risk of harm; all decisions are contingent on the
prediction and consideration of risks and benefits. This line of argument
does not support the view that a type of research is intrinsically
immoral. The differentiation between
nonconsequentialists and consequentialists suitably characterizes two
extreme approaches to the evaluation of a new technology. In practice,
however, advocates and opponents of modern biotechnology often combine
consequentialist and nonconsequentialist elements. |
|
|
|
For example, Greenpeace's slogan
"no genetic manipulation of nature" (http://www.greenpeace.org/~geneng/)
appears to describe a moral limit. In reality, however, Greenpeace debates
the issue using science and (consequentialist) risk language. Greenpeace
is not alone. In the public debate, all opponents are pressed to provide a
whole list of arguments that often have the structure: first, genetic
engineering is absolutely wrong; and second, the projected risks are too
high considering the projected benefits. This prompts the question: Why do
we need to add a risk argument after stating the moral argument? The absolutist, nonconsequentialist
moral prescription would trump the contingent risk argument in any
case—even if the balance of benefits and risk would call for the use of
biotechnology on consequentialist moral grounds, as the industry keeps
arguing. Perhaps the moral language is just a metaphor to strongly suggest
a conclusion reached on the basis of (consequentialist) risk. I would call
this position "the prescription of a metaphorical moral limit." The problem with this approach is that
it lacks clarity. Is a metaphorical moral limit specified to illustrate
that the consequences are thought to be so severe that only an absolute
prohibition will do? Or, is risk language used to convince science-minded
individuals who may not be inclined to accept the true reason, the real
moral limit specified first? Lack of clarity on this point fuels the
rhetoric in the debate. It is perhaps helpful here to consider
an ethical prescription of the second order—a prescription for the way
ethical prescriptions should be used in this debate. I believe it is, in
principle, defensible to argue for the prohibition of a technological
method on moral grounds, even when the argument is based on an extension
of traditional moral limits (e.g., an extension from a human-centered
approach to one not centered on humans). I note in this context that
religious freedom is a human right. I further believe it is defensible to
scrutinize closely the control structure over vital resources, such as
food and health care, or to scrutinize closely the conditions for release
of persistent technologies that may be hard to trace or manage, and in
cases in which it is difficult to assign liabilities. However, I do not
believe it defensible to call for prohibition when tight regulation is in
order, or to argue for tight regulation as a tactic toward achieving the
real goal of prohibition. Similarly, if the primary goal is
profit, then one should avoid the argument that "we have to feed the
world." The use of imprecise language or rhetoric entails a very real
cost: when it becomes necessary to alter one's stance over time, then
credibility and trust are at risk. A loss of credibility and trust hurts
advocates in both camps—and most of all, the public. In a nutshell, a second-order viewpoint
of the ethical debate leads to a straightforward prescription. If we want
fairness, respect, and progress in this debate, then we all have to say
what we really mean. |
Category: 4. Ethical and Social Concerns Arising out of Biotechnology