Brain Death

 

Outline

      Truog argues that the concept of brain death (as currently understood) is inconsistent and that it might be best to abandon it altogether

    Describes concept

    Shows that it is internally inconsistent

    Considers alternative criteria for determining death has occurred

    Concludes that we should return to the cardiorespiratory standard

    Works out the implications of his conclusion for organ donation

 

Brain Death

      Traditional view: death has occurred when breathing and heart beat cease

      BUT we can now use machines to replace heart and lung function

      “Brain death” has therefore become an accepted standard

 

Why is brain death a good alternative standard?

      Allows for action in cases where attempts to revive an individual are unsuccessful: can stop mechanical support without committing euthanasia

      Agrees with our intuition regarding personhood (who we are depends on our brain…)

      Permits organs to be harvested for transplant

 

The “whole brain” standard

President’s Commission, 1981

             Irreversible cessation of circulatory or respiratory functions OR

             Irreversible cessation of all functions of the entire brain, including the brain stem

         The first is an indication of the second

 

Three levels of analysis

             Definition of death: “permanent cessation of functioning of the organism as a whole”

             Criterion for death: “permanent cessation of function of the entire brain”

             Tests for death: cardiorespiratory tests or neurological tests

 

Definition, criterion, tests?

             What is death?

           Definition answers this question

 

             How do we know death has occurred?

           Criterion gives a general standard

           Tests are more specific

 

Tests

      Cardiorespiratory standard – prolonged absence of vital signs

   This standard also fulfills the criterion of cardiorespiratory death

      Neurological standard – battery of tests and procedures.  Includes knowledge of etiology.

 

Are these levels consistent?

      If “yes,” the definition, criterion and tests must all be consistent

      That is, (1) fulfilling the medical tests must mean satisfying the criterion and (2) satisfying the criterion must mean satisfying the definition

      Truog: neither (1) nor (2) are true; concept of brain death is not consistent

 

      Tests/criterion are not consistent:

   An individual who “fails” the tests may still have some brain activity: body temperature, hormonal homeostasis.  Also physiological response to surgical incision at organ removal.

   Using the cardiorespiratory standard instead guarantees that the person judged dead is actually dead, but means that organs cannot be harvested

             Can they be made consistent?

         Better neurological tests

        Not likely

         Reliance on cardiorespiratory test only

        But law would prohibit organ donation

 

             Criterion/definition are not consistent

         The whole brain concept assumes that the criterion necessarily implies the definition

         This view is based on the fact that the brain regulates homeostasis; if the brain is not functioning properly, then “the organism rapidly disintegrates”

 

   But “rapid disintegration” means that the organism is dying not that it is dead.  So the criterion is not diagnostic of death, but prognostic.

   Also assumes that the brain is irreplaceable – but the ICU can act as a “surrogate brainstem”

   Pregnant women who are brain dead

   Brain dead patients awaiting organ harvesting

 

Why do we want consistency?

      May not need it if we can still set good policy

      But, medicine does seek to be based on a solid theoretical and conceptual basis

      Also, there is evidence to link this inconsistency with confusion among clinicians, laypersons

   Good reasons for avoiding this confusion

Two Alternatives…

…to the whole-brain criterion

 

             “Higher brain” criterion

             Return to cardiorespiratory standard

 

Higher-Brain Criterion

      Death would be identified with permanent loss of consciousness

      This accords with our understanding of what it means to be a person (“higher” brain functions)

      Would include two groups not included by current “whole-brain standard”

    Permanent vegetative state

    Anencephalic newborns

      There would be problems with this standard, as well

   Diagnosis of permanent unconsciousness is difficult

   Distinction between death of the person and death of the organism

   Breathing, but dead?

   Burial or cremation

   “Living remains”

 

Cardiorespiratory Criterion

      This is the traditional criterion; Truog considers whether we should return to it

      He looks at the reasons that it was initially rejected in favour of the current whole-brain standard

 

Truog identifies four questions addressed by the Harvard committee:

            When is it permissible to withdraw life support for the benefit of the patient?

            …for the benefit of society?

           When is it permissible to remove organs?

           When is a person ready to be buried?

             The Harvard Committee gave one answer to all of these questions

             Considering them separately may give us a better way to find an alternative to brain death

 

1. Withdrawal of life support

      Harvard committee: brain death as necessary condition for withdrawal of life support

      Since then, there has been a change in the acceptability of withdrawing treatment – the wishes of the patient (or surrogate) are followed

 

2. Allocation of scarce resources

      Should patients with a hopeless prognosis occupy scarce ICU beds?

      This problem is actually rare (in part because of withdrawal of treatment) and so has little impact on resource availability

 

4.  When should a person be cremated or buried?

      “Even today we uniformly regard the cessation of respiration and circulation as the standard for determining when patients are ready to be cremated or buried.”

      Greater degree of agreement about this than about brain death (some religious and cultural traditions do not accept the concept of brain death)

 

Organ Donation in Canada

      2006 – 3974 patients waiting for organ donation (up from 2592 in 1995)

      Canada has 12.8 donors per million population

   Spain has 35.1

   U.S. has 21.5

   Belgium 22.8

 

      Nearly 98% of kidney transplants, 90% of liver transplants and 85% of heart transplants are successful

      Canadian practice – those willing to donate “opt in” through signing an organ donor card, or through explicit consent of surviving family

 

      Canadian Council for Donation and Transplantation established by Health Canada in 2001

   Raise public awareness about the need for donor organs

   Improve coordination of donor process between regions, provinces

 

3.  Organ transplantation

      Truog: the most important question

      Is brain death an ethical and legal justification for harvesting organs?

      Some attempts have been made to circumvent the need for a diagnosis of brain death before organ harvesting

      Methods and justifications of these protocols is “contrived and even somewhat bizarre”

       “How can the legitimate desire to increase the supply of transplantable organs be reconciled with the need to maintain a clear and simple distinction between the living and the dead?”

      Could abandon criterion for brain death and focus instead on ethical criteria, such as consent, nonmaleficence

       “Even now, surveys show that one-third of physicians and nurses do not believe brain-dead patients are actually dead, but feel comfortable with the process of organ procurement because the patients are permanently unconscious and/or imminently dying.”

Different definitions?

      One alternative – different definitions of death depending on purpose or preference?

      Purposes: one definition for organ harvesting and another for burial

      Preference: individuals could choose a definition of death that ranged from cardiorespiratory standard through to permanent unconsciousness (Emanuel)

    Would permit individuals to request or to reject organ donation, depending on the definition they choseA dilemma

      We want to be able to procure transplantable organs and we want a conceptually coherent account of death…

   Current standards for organ donation require brain death

   Current standards re burial (“real death”?) require cardiorespiratory death

 

A solution?

      Truog suggests that we solve the dilemma by returning to the cardiorespiratory definition of death and saying that “killing may sometimes be a justifiable necessity for procuring transplantable organs”

 

Justification of organ harvesting

      Troug’s suggestion would require that we find a different justification for harvesting organs

   Current justification is that (1) the patient is dead and (2) the patient/family have given permission

 

      The return to the cardiorespiratory standard would mean that we would be killing a living person in order to harvest his/her organs

      To justify this, we would need (1) consent/permission and (2) principle of nonmaleficence

   Could only harvest organs from someone who would not be harmed by the procedure

 

Consent?

      Ontario: recent proposed change from “opting in” for organ donation to “opting out”

   Tacit consent

      Would this change our views on whether we could harvest organs from someone who is still “technically” alive?

   Is nonmaleficence enough?

 

Gaylin

      Raises a similar point to Wikler, but arrives at it differently:

      “Pulling the plug” on a brain dead patient is not viewed as euthanasia because the patient is dead

      But if brain death “grants the right to pull the plug, it also implicitly grants the privilege not to pull the plug”

 

Enter the neomort

      Cadavers maintained on life support would be legally dead, but would be “warm, respiring, pulsating, evacuating and excreting bodies requiring nursing, dietary and general grooming attention”

 

We now permit and accept

      Dead donors

   Autopsies

   Use of cadavers for teaching purposes

   Organ donation

      Living donors

   Tissue/cell donation (blood and compounds, sperm), also skin, muscle transplants

 

Why not use neomorts?

      “Whatever is possible with the old embalmed cadaver is extended to an incredible degree with the neomort”

   Training (physical examination, diagnostic procedures, surgical techniques”

   Testing (drug physiology, toxicology)

   Experiments (instead of animal research)

   Banking of organs, tissues

   Harvesting of organs as needed

   “Manufacture” of hormones, antibodies

 

Cost-benefit analysis:
economic issues

      If we can find one economically sound reason for maintaining neomorts, we get all of the other benefits “for free” (gratuitous byproducts)

      Switching to a “higher brain” rather than “whole brain” definition of brain death would save money

 

Cost-benefit analysis:
other costs?

      “Cost-benefit analysis is always least satisfactory when the costs must be measured in one realm and the benefits in another.”

   What would the costs be of using neomorts?

 

The “Ick” factor

      What is the source of the problem that many people have with neomorts?

    Autopsies

    Abdominal surgery

    Disposing of the dead (cremation, organ donation)

    Test-tube babies

    Cloning

      Is the “ick factor” a product of ignorance and superstition or a sign that we have reached a boundary that we shouldn’t cross?