Euthanasia
•
From Greek: “good death” or
“easy death”
•
Sometimes referred to as
“mercy killing”
•
Some distinctions
–
Voluntary/nonvoluntary/involuntary
–
Active/passive
euthanasia/physician-assisted suicide
–
Is patient prognosis relevant?
Nancy B.
[1992]
•
Became ill in June, 1989,
diagnosed with Guillain-Barré syndrome
–
Rare (1 or 2 per 100,000/year)
–
Patients usually recover
completely
•
Motor paralysis, may include
diaphragm
•
Nancy B. intubated, placed on
respirator
•
January 1991, condition
declared irreversible (degeneration of muscles)
•
Withdrew consent for therapy
(respirator)
–
Aware of consequences
–
Discussed condition with
physicians
–
Was deemed competent
(psychiatric evaluation)
•
Sought a court injunction to
require hospital/physician to remove the respirator
• Judge ruled that the respirator should be
removed
–
“The logical corollary of the
right to consent is the right not to consent”
–
Nancy B. was competent and so
deserved to have her autonomy respected
–
A person who removed the
respirator at Nancy B.’s request (thus, acted as her agent) would not be
vulnerable to criminal sanction because s/he would be allowing a natural death
rather than assisting the patient to commit suicide
Sue
Rodriguez [1993]
•
Had been diagnosed with ALS
(Lou Gehrig’s disease) in 1991: would lose motor function gradually (including
the ability to breathe)
•
Did not want to die when she
could still enjoy life and so did not want to commit suicide before her
condition deteriorated
•
Wanted the right to end her
life with the help of a physician when she could no longer commit suicide for
herself
•
Became an activist, trying to
change Canadian laws against assisted suicide – case went to the Supreme Court
of Canada
–
Section 241(b) of Criminal
Code – it’s an offense to aid or abet someone in committing suicide
•
1993 – Court refuses to change
law, but the decision was close (5-4)
•
Majority judgment: section of the Criminal Code prohibiting
assisted suicide did impinge upon Rodriguez’s Charter rights, but this was
justifiable under another section (1) of the Charter, saying that rights could
be infringed upon if I was “demonstrably justified in a free and democratic
nation”
•
Justice à preserve the sanctity of life
•
Sopinka also cited the
possibility for abuse if law against assisted suicide were repealed
–
Slippery slope argument (if
we allow A, then B will occur – where B is clearly unacceptable)
•
Dissenting judgments (3):
discrimination on the basis of disability, called for a constitutional
exemption from law in Rodriguez’s case pending review of issue by Parliament
– But the actual act of ending her life should be
committed by Rodriguez herself
Brock
•
Focuses on voluntary active
euthanasia (and physician assisted suicide)
•
Starts by citing an “emerging
consensus” that competent patients (or their surrogates) should be able to
weigh the benefits and burdens of alternative treatment, including no treatment
(passive euthanasia)
Brock’s
Primary Aim
•
“…to identify confusions in
some common arguments [regarding voluntary active euthanasia] and problematic
assumptions and claims in others”
Outline
•
Clarify terminology
•
Overview of main argument for
euthanasia
•
Two kinds of argument against
–
moral
–
policy
Voluntary
Active Euthanasia and Physician-Assisted Suicide
•
The paradigm case of
physician-assisted suicide: the physician supplies a lethal drug and the
patient uses it to end her life
•
The paradigm case of voluntary
active euthanasia: The physician administers the lethal dose to the patient
•
Brock: there is no substantive
moral difference between these two situations
–
“what if a physician gave a
patient lethal medication knowing that the patient would then administer it to
someone else?”
•
Since no moral
difference, should be no policy difference
Argument
for Voluntary Active Euthanasia
•
The same two fundamental
ethical values that underlie the consensus on a patient’s right to decide about
life-sustaining treatment also support the right to euthanasia. These values are:
–
Individual
self-determination/autonomy
–
Individual well-being
Self-determination
•
Refers to people’s right to
make important decisions about their lives for themselves that accord with
their own values or their own conception of a good life. Also the freedom to act on these decisions.
Self-determination
regarding death
• People often respond to the thought of death with fear
of suffering, desire to retain dignity and control, desire to be remembered in
a certain way
• Technology in health care means that for many people,
death is/will be preceded by a long period of physical/mental decline
• No single objective point at which this decline makes
life a burden: thus need for self-determination
Individual
well-being
•
Similar to “self-interest” –
the assumption that we act in line with our own best interests
•
But can it ever be in our best
interests to die?
–
Quality of life
–
Life as burden, not benefit
–
Again, no objective standard
Two caveats
•
Problem of clinically
depressed patients (and illness, especially terminal illness, may cause or
worsen depression)
•
Does not compel
physicians to act contrary to their own values à there are limits on what a patient can ask a
physician to do
Opponents
to Euthanasia
•
Two kinds of argument
–
Euthanasia is ethically wrong
(moral argument)
–
Euthanasia is ethically
permissible but still should not be permitted (policy argument)
1.
Euthanasia is wrong…
•
It is the deliberate killing
of an innocent person
•
Brock’s reply: euthanasia is killing, but is morally
permissible
Doctors
don’t kill
•
“In the context of medicine,
the ethical prohibition against deliberately killing the innocent derives some
of its plausibility from the belief that nothing in the currently accepted
practice of medicine is deliberate killing.”
–
“Killing” vs. “letting die”
(active/passive)
The Greedy
Son
•
There are important ethical
differences between the doctor’s actions and those of the greedy son:
•
Patient’s consent
•
Different motives
•
Socially-sanctioned role: doctor is authorized to carry out patient’s
wishes
Rachels
•
Brock’s example: it’s not the
“passive” in passive euthanasia that makes it morally acceptable
–
No difference between active
and passive euthanasia
•
Rachels – also argues that
there is no moral difference between active and passive euthanasia
Killing vs.
Letting Die
•
Why do people want to make
this distinction?
–
Killing as “unjustified”
causing of death. Withdrawing of
life-sustaining treatment is justified in a medical context
•
Psychological discomfort with
the idea that doctors kill (shifts responsibility to the disease)
Paradigm
cases, again
•
Brock: even if euthanasia is
killing, it could still be morally permissible:
–
It differs from the paradigm
case of killing in another important way
–
In the paradigm case, killing
takes something of value (life) away from the victim – this is a large part of
why killing is wrong
–
In euthanasia, the “victim” no
longer values her life
2. Policy arguments
• Even if euthanasia is morally permissible, there are
good legal and policy reasons not to permit it
– Brock:
these arguments are stronger than the strictly ethical ones
• Different types of policy argument may disagree about:
– What
consequences might follow permitting euthanasia
– The
relative moral importance of these consequences
Good
consequences of allowing euthanasia
•
Respects the
self-determination of competent patients (but we need to consider the
importance/weight we should give to this good consequence; this also requires
that we look at alternatives to euthanasia)
•
Provides reassurance to those
who feel they might someday want the option of euthanasia
•
“Argument from mercy”
•
Applies to those whose dying
would otherwise be filled with pain and suffering (physical or psychological)
Potential
Bad Consequences
•
Performing euthanasia is
incompatible with physicians’ role as healer – allowing euthanasia will change
the way we see physicians
•
Would weaken society’s resolve
to provide care to the dying ($)
•
Would threaten the right to
refuse life-saving treatment (increased involvement of courts)
•
Need for they dying to justify
their continued existence (“the existence of the option [of euthanasia] becomes
a subtle pressure to request it”)
•
Will weaken the general
prohibition against homicide
•
The slippery slope argument
-
voluntary euthanasia is
morally permissible, but if we allow it, then it’s only a matter of time before
we allow nonvoluntary euthanasia, involuntary euthanasia
Brock re
the slippery slope
•
This scenario is possible, but
is it likely?
–
No evidence (speculation)
–
Also, can put safeguards in
place to prevent descent down the slippery slope
Brock’s
recommended safeguards
•
Patient should be given all
relevant information
•
There should be a waiting
period (to make sure that the request is stable) – and should also make sure it
is truly voluntary (not due to pressure from others)
•
All reasonable alternatives
must be explored for pain relief, increasing QOL, etc.
•
There should be a psychiatric
evaluation to rule out depression
Nonvoluntary
euthanasia
•
Brock also suggests that, in
some cases, nonvoluntary euthanasia might be morally permissible
•
In the case of incompetent
individuals, surrogates make their medical decisions – this might well extend
to the request for euthanasia
•
In some cases, the surrogate
expresses the wishes the patient had when competent
•
In other cases, the patient’s
wishes are unknown – this raises the possibility of abuse
•
Brock – should put better
safeguards in place for all end-of-life decision-making, not just
euthanasia