Introduction to Resource Allocation
Resource
Allocation
•
The
issue of resource allocation in health care is complex and requires input from
a number of groups/disciplines
•
The
need to make decisions about resourced allocation arises from the fact that the
demand for health care resources is virtually infinite; the supply
is much less!
•
We
need to decide, then, how much of our resources should be used for health care
and which health care needs to satisfy
•
As
health care becomes more successful and more technical, it also becomes more
expensive
– New therapies, improved therapies
– Chronic diseases
– Aging population (contributes to
increased demand)
– Economic factors
– Higher expectations (?)
McGregor
(1989)
Until recently: “The principle cost involved in health
services was for the comfort and support of the sick, and this cost was
relatively low because patients either recovered or succumbed fairly
rapidly. The interventions that
medicine could make in the course of disease were so slight that a doctor could
carry almost all equipment of importance around in a little black bag.”
What
we’ll be focusing on:
•
November
19, 21: Introduction, overview of issues & problems, the Romanow report
•
November
26, 28: Macro-allocation – the case of IVF treatment
•
December
3, 5: Micro-allocation – issues in organ transplantation
What
are the issues?
•
How
much funding for health care?
•
Who
should fund what?
•
What
to treat/fund?
•
How
to decide what to treat/fund?
•
Who
should decide what to treat/fund?
•
How
to distribute available care among individuals
What
must be considered?
•
Ethical
issues (e.g. distributive justice)
•
Economic
issues (e.g. cost control, efficiency)
•
Medical
issues (e.g. “medical necessity,” what is “health)
•
Empirical
issues (e.g. which treatments are effective? How effective are they?)
•
Social
issues (e.g. values of the population in question)
Rationing
vs. Allocation
•
“Historically,
‘to ration’ has meant ‘to distribute equitably,’ so a notion of fairness or
justice has been intrinsic to the understanding of rationing.”
•
More
recently, the term has come to be associated with the idea of deciding which
needs to meet
“In the United States, it has even been
proposed that ‘rationing’ be used to mean ‘societal toleration of inequitable
access (e.g. based on ability to pay) to services deemed necessary, as defined
by reference to appropriate clinical guidelines’”
Hoffmaster, citing Hadorn &
Brook, JAMA, 1991
“Levels”
of resource allocation
•
Macro
allocation: at the level of the
government. What proportion of a
society’s budget will go to health care? (federal and provinicial) How will
this money be distributed within the area of health care (e.g.
diagnostic and therapeutic services, hospital budgets, drugs, physician
salaries, preventive medicine, rehabilitation) (provinicial)
•
Meso
allocation: hospitals and other organizations providing health care services
must decide how to distribute the budget they receive from the government
across their various divisions and services
– The ethical issues arising at this
level of resource allocation have been less studied than the other two levels
•
Micro
allocation: made in the case of individual patients, primarily by physicians:
how extensive should diagnostic tests be? How aggressively to treat
disease? When to discontinue
rehabilitation.
•
Much
writing on micro allocation looks at situations in which resources are scarce:
how to adjudicate between competing claims to limited resources
Rationing
vs. allocation, again
•
“Allocation”
generally used to refer to higher level decisions that constrain the
availability of resources
•
“Rationing”
generally used to refer to decisions about how resources that have been limited
(through allocation decisions) should be used
Macro
allocation:
What
should be funded?
Who should decide?
Demarcation
•
A
principle of demarcation is a criterion that divides a group of things into two
groups. In the case of resource
allocation, such a principle would be used to determine what should and should
not be funded.
•
The
question, then, is what kind of principle should be used…
1. Cost effectiveness
•
What
if we fund the most cost-effective treatments?
This way, we can benefit the greatest number of people
•
But,
this would mean that it would be more important to fund tooth capping than
appendectomies. We need to figure out a
way to compare dissimilar treatments.
2. How beneficial is the treatment?
•
We
want to fund the things that will do the most good…i.e. that give the best net
benefits
•
But
we also need to consider the starting point.
What if we have two treatments that give equal net benefits, but one
treatment is for a condition that is associated with poor functioning and the
other with a condition that is associated with moderate functioning?
3.
Medical Necessity
•
A
demarcation principle based on medical necessity says that we should fund only
medically necessary treatments
•
Freedman
and Baylis: (a) this approach is intuitively plausible and in some cases is the
only possible approach, but in other cases it “results in some obvious
inequalities and distortions in government coverage practices”
•
Freedman
and Baylis: (b) We also need a concept
of medical necessity. But it’s
notoriously difficult to define health…
•
WHO
definition: “Health is a state of complete physical, mental and social
well-being and not merely the absence of disease.”
•
Callahan:
On this definition, crime, poverty and other social problems are medical
problems…the definition is too inclusive
Macro
Allocation:
Health Care Funding
in Canada
Health
Care Funding in Canada
•
Provinces/territories
responsible for most funding decisions; in many provinces, regional health
authorities make specific funding decisions
•
Canada Health Act (1984) sets conditions on health care funding –
funding to provinces is reduced (dollar-for-dollar) if provinces or physicians
charge user fees for certain services
•
In practice, “five
conditions” of the CHA have come to represent principles underlying
Canadian Medicare policy: public administration, comprehensiveness,
universality, portability, accessibility
Health
care in Canada
•
Who
pays?
–
We do: health
services in Canada are funded by tax revenue, by private insurance (often
through employers) and by out-of-pocket spending
–
The publicly-funded
part (~70%) is funded through transfer payments from the federal government to
the provinces, which make decisions about how to spend the money (within the
terms stipulated by the federal Canada Health Act)
–
Private funding (~30%)
comes from out-of-pocket payments by individuals or by private insurance
What
things are publicly funded?
•
Primarily
in-hospital care and physician services, dental surgery (in hospitals) and
nursing homes
– These seem to be the core of what we
value…
•
Some
provinces also cover some aspects of prescription drugs, home care, long-term
care, rehabilitation/physiotherapy
– These things are “negotiable” – e.g.
annual eye examinations in Ontario
Private
insurance/out-of-pocket spending
•
Dental
care
•
Vision
care
•
Prescription
drugs
•
Physiotherapy/massage/chiropractic
•
CAM
therapies and medicines
The
Romanow Report
•
Report
of the Royal Commission on the Future of Health Care in Canada (headed by Roy
Romanow) – released in 2002
•
Found
that, in general, Canadians value a universally accessible, publicly-funded
health care system
•
But
they also worry about “sustainability”
•
The
Commission noted that “sustainability” requires more than a focus on money:
need to ensure that sufficient resources are available (including health care
providers, facilities, technologies, resources for research)
•
Should
guarantee timely access, quality of service, flexibility to suit changing needs
What’s
good about this…
•
Guaranteed
level of basic care for everyone
•
The
system is flexible enough to consider cases in which people have “extra” needs,
e.g. prescription coverage for seniors
What’s
not good…
•
Health
care needs (and our technical ability to fulfill those needs) are changing
faster than our health care system
– High tech medicine
– Prescription drugs
The BIG
issue: Private, for-profit service delivery
•
Hospitals
are generally non-profit
•
Most
physician services are delivered through what are “effectively owner-operated
small businesses” (but what these
businesses can charge is regulated)
•
Large,
for-profit organizations deliver some services, e.g. laboratory testing,
long-term care
•
Should
we increase the amount of private, for-profit service delivery?
•
What
services should be candidates for privatization?
A
distinction:
•
Direct
health care services: medical, diagnostic, surgical care
•
Ancillary
services: e.g. laundry, cleaning, food preparation
– In general, people find it more
acceptable for these services to be privatized: this is because (1) there are
alternatives in terms of choosing who should provide these services and (2)
it’s easier to judge the quality of these services
•
There
are currently some companies/individuals providing private, for-profit direct
health care:
– Approximately 300 clinics delivering
services formerly provided (only) in hospitals: abortions, endoscopic surgery,
physiotherapy, in vitro fertilization, laser eye surgery
•
Some
clinics/hospitals provide more complex surgeries (requiring overnight stays)
Hurley:
Ethical and Economic Issues in Health Care Funding
•
Is
there an ethical rationale for publicly-funded health insurance?
–
A number of
different arguments, rooted in different ethical frameworks
–
All arguments have
a similar structure:
•
Ultimate
purpose of human life/society
•
Role of
health and its distribution in advancing this purpose
•
Role of
access to/use of health care in maintaining or improving the health of members
of society
•
Role of
public financing in ensuring (ethically justified) access to/use of health care
Ethics
and Economics…
•
“economic
analysis is a necessary ingredient” in discussion of the ethical rationale for
public funding, since we need to show that the ethical distribution of health
care resources cannot be achieved through private financing alone
– Conceptual issues à what goals should we have?
– Empirical (incl. economic) issues à does a specific system allow us to
meet these goals?
Hurley’s
paper
•
Organizes
paper around 4 questions described above (esp. #3 and #4)
•
Uses
three ethical frameworks to illustrate key points:
– Classical utilitarianism
– Extra-welfarism
– Contractrianism (Rawls)
Ethical
frameworks
•
Classical
utilitarianism: actions/policies should promote happiness (utility)
•
Extra-welfarism:
policies should ensure that people have specific capabilities/ functionings
•
Rawls’s
contractarianism: inequalities should be tolerated only when they improve the
circumstances of the worst-off
The
Purpose of Life…
•
Different
political theories give different accounts of the purpose of life (e.g.
happiness/utility, satisfaction of rational desires (rational plan of life)
•
Health
is seen as an instrumental good; that is, it is good because it allows us to
achieve these ultimate goals of life (and also intermediate goals…)
Health
and Society
•
What
does our ethical analysis of choice demand regarding the just distribution of
health in society?
– Health is only one means that leads
us to our desired ends
– Health cannot be directly
redistributed
The
distribution of health
•
What
should we demand in terms of health distribution?
– That all have equal health?
– That average health is maximized?
– That all have a guaranteed minimum
level of health?
– That the least advantaged are
benefited?
Distributing
health care
•
Health
care = “those goods, services and activities the primary purpose of which is
the maintenance or improvement of health”
•
The
ethically-justified distribution of health care is the one that leads to the
appropriate level and distribution of health
Access
and need
•
We
also need to distinguish between access to health care resources and need of
those resources
•
Both
concepts can be defined differently and there is disagreement about the
appropriate definitions
•
What
is important is that people have access to needed services
•
The
issue of effectiveness is also important (this may include cost-effectiveness) à we only want to fund health care
that makes a (sufficiently large) difference to people’s health
•
Different
ethical frameworks have different views on the relationship between access and
need, but all of the ones we’ve discussed accept that access should be
associated with need, rather than ability to pay
The
role of public financing
•
Public
financing is necessary to generate the ethically justified distribution of
access and use OR
•
Public
financing does this better than other financing arrangements
•
Showing
that one of these claims is true requires comparing alternative financing
arrangements (Hurley discusses four…)
1. Fully private insurance
•
Market
regulates the provision of health care
•
The
unpredictability of health care needs means that few people can be sure that
they will be able to pay out-of-pocket for health expenses
•
Therefore,
there is an important role for health insurance (pooling risk)
•
But
a fully private insurance scheme cannot guarantee broad access
•
Markets
allocate goods and services based on the ability to pay
•
Low-income
members of a society may not be able to pay for adequate health insurance
(especially since insurance premiums will reflect an assessment of the
individual’s level of risk…)
2. Public subsidies of private insurance
•
We
could have public funds pay insurance premiums for those who can’t afford to
pay them themselves
•
OR
we could provide publicly-funded insurance some of the population (e.g. U.S.
Medicare/Medicaid)
•
This
approach relies on health markets being “otherwise well-functioning”
•
“Well-functioning” here means efficient; in
economics, a situation is efficient when we cannot increase one beneficial
activity without decreasing another
•
But
health care markets are not efficient
– Fixed cost to insurers of providing
insurance (e.g. calculating premiums) and administrative costs
•
But
health care markets are not efficient
– Fixed cost to insurers of providing
insurance (e.g. calculating premiums) and administrative costs
– Difficult to ensure that insurance
“use” reflects risk
– Asymmetry of information between
patients and health care providers means that health care providers can
recommend use of health resources in a way that is not efficient
Key
messages
•
It
is more costly to produce insurance through private markets
•
Private
markets will lead to incomplete coverage
•
“Cost
sharing” will not occur in an appropriate way in private health insurance
3. Public/private mix
•
Some
countries allow individuals to purchase private insurance for publicly-funded
services
– Benefits to individuals: wider range
of treatment choices, queue jumping
– System benefits: Advocates say that
this type of system will remove demand from the public system by removing
demand
Effects
of private insurance
•
This
type of system is not directly contradictory to many ethical systems (only to
those ethical systems that demand equal access, or that want to ensure equal
maximum possible consumption of health care)
•
It
could be compatible with ethical frameworks that demand maximized average
health, guaranteed minimum health, benefit to least advantaged
•
But
this is just “possible” (“in principle”) compatibility – we also need to show
that, in practice, a mixed system like this one is compatible with these
ethical demands
•
Hurley
cites evidence that they are not:
–
Can drain resources
(esp. “human resources” from the public system)
–
Can erode public
support for the public system à less money available so less services (wait times)
–
Can increase
overall health costs, esp. by increasing use of services that generate smaller
health gains
•
Advocates
of this type of system: parallel private system would reduce demand on public
system by providing an additional new source of supply
•
Hurley:
this supply would not merely be an “add-on” – “Complex interactions occur that
affect the viability of the publicly financed system”
•
Resources
will be taken from the public system in a way that’s incompatible with the
ethical principles we described above
No
Public Funding?
Libertarianism
•
The
ethical systems that Hurley considers all agree that some restrictions on
individual rights should occur to benefit society as a whole and/or those
members of a society that are least advantaged (financially, in terms of
health, etc.)
•
Libertarians
value individual freedom of choice – restriction on individual freedom is
rarely/never justified
•
Public
funding of health care is bad because it:
–
Reduces
people’s free choice about how to seek and use health care/insurance
–
Forces
people to contribute financially to a publicly-funded system (via taxes)
•
We
can describe this view as valuing autonomy over all other ethical principles
(particularly distributive justice)
•
Few people would
take the view that there should be no provision of health care for those
who are not able to pay for their own care or insurance
•
But there are
disagreements about how much the public provision of this care should be
allowed to restrict individual choices
•
Hurley’s arguments:
effects of individual choices reduce ability of public system to provide
care. Libertarian response – this is a
problem with the public system, not with private insurance (clash between
“ultimate” values shifts burden of proof…”
The
distribution of health
•
What
should we demand in terms of health distribution?
– That all have equal health?
– That average health is maximized?
– That all have a guaranteed minimum
level of health?
– That the least advantaged are
benefited?
–
That
people be free to pursue their individual health goals (and all other goals)