Euthanasia
I: Ethical Issues
Euthanasia
•
From Greek: “good death” or
“easy death”
•
Sometimes referred to as
“mercy killing”
•
Some distinctions
–
Voluntary/nonvoluntary/involuntary
–
Active/passive
Brock
•
Focuses on voluntary active
euthanasia
•
Starts by citing an “emerging
consensus” that competent patients (or their surrogates) should be able to
weigh the benefits and burdens of alternative treatment, including no treatment
(passive euthanasia)
Brock’s
Primary Aim
•
“…to identify confusions in
some common arguments [regarding voluntary active euthanasia] and problematic
assumptions and claims in others”
Outline
•
Clarify terminology
•
Overview of main argument for
euthanasia
•
Two arguments against
euthanasia
–
One at personal/moral level
–
One at policy level
Voluntary
Active Euthanasia and Physician-Assisted Suicide
•
The paradigm case of
physician-assisted suicide: the physician supplies a lethal drug and the
patient uses it to end her life
•
The paradigm case of voluntary
active euthanasia: The physician administers the lethal dose to the patient
•
Brock: there is no substantive
moral difference between these two situations
–
“what if a physician gave a
patient lethal medication knowing that the patient would then administer it to
someone else?”
Argument
for Voluntary Active Euthanasia
•
The same two fundamental
ethical values that underlie the consensus on a patient’s right to decide about
life-sustaining treatment also support the right to euthanasia. These values are:
–
Individual
self-determination/autonomy
–
Individual well-being
Self-determination
•
Refers to people’s right to
make important decisions about their lives for themselves that accord with
their own values or their own conception of a good life. Also the freedom to act on these decisions.
Self-determination
regarding death
• People often respond to the thought of death with fear
of suffering, desire to retain dignity and control, desire to be remembered in
a certain way
• Technology in health care means that for many people,
death is/will be preceded by a long period of physical/mental decline
• No single objective point at which this decline makes
life a burden: thus need for self-determination
Individual
well-being
•
Similar to “self-interest” –
the assumption that we act in line with our own best interests
•
But can it ever be in our best
interests to die?
–
Quality of life
–
Life as burden, not benefit
–
Again, no objective standard
Two caveats
•
Problem of clinically
depressed patients (and illness, especially terminal illness, may cause or
worsen depression)
•
Does not compel
physicians to act contrary to their own values à there are limits on what a patient can ask a
physician to do
Opponents
to Euthanasia
•
Two kinds of argument
–
Euthanasia is ethically wrong
–
Euthanasia is ethically
permissible but still should not be permitted
Euthanasia
is wrong…
•
It is the deliberate killing
of an innocent person
–
Paradigm case of murder vs.
euthanasia
•
Brock: euthanasia is killing, but is morally
permissible
Doctors
don’t kill
•
“In the context of medicine,
the ethical prohibition against deliberately killing the innocent derives some
of its plausibility from the belief that nothing in the currently accepted
practice of medicine is deliberate killing.”
–
“Killing” vs. “letting die”
(active/passive)
Rachels
•
Active vs. passive euthanasia
– there is no real distinction
•
Classic article
–
Short! (two journal pages)
–
Controversial (because
challenges the common view that the distinction is real)
Back to
Brock…
•
There are important ethical
differences between the doctor’s actions and those of the greedy son:
•
Patient’s consent
•
Different motives
•
Socially-sanctioned role:
doctor is authorized to carry out patient’s wishes
Paradigm
cases, again
•
Brock: even if both euthanasia
is killing, it could still be morally permissible:
–
It differs from the paradigm
case of killing in another important way
–
In the paradigm case, killing
takes something of value (life) away from the victim – this is a large part of
why killing is wrong
–
In euthanasia, the “victim” no
longer values her life
Policy
arguments
•
Even if euthanasia is morally
permissible, there are good legal and policy reasons not to permit it
•
Brock: these arguments are
stronger than the strictly ethical ones (these arguments are not ‘strictly
ethical’ because they have both empirical and moral aspects)
Good
consequences of allowing euthanasia
•
Respects the
self-determination of competent patients (but we need to consider the importance/weight
we should give to this good consequence; this also requires that we look at
alternatives to euthanasia)
•
Provides reassurance to those
who feel they might someday want the option of euthanasia
•
“Argument from mercy”
•
Applies to those whose dying
would otherwise be filled with pain and suffering (physical or psychological)
Potential
Bad Consequences
•
Performing euthanasia is
incompatible with physicians’ role as healer – allowing euthanasia will change
the way we see physicians
•
Would weaken society’s resolve
to provide care to the dying ($)
•
Would threaten the right to
refuse life-saving treatment (increased involvement of courts)
•
Need for they dying to justify
their continued existence (“the existence of the option [of euthanasia] becomes
a subtle pressure to request it”)
•
Will weaken the general
prohibition against homicide
•
The slippery slope argument
-
voluntary euthanasia is
morally permissible, but if we allow it, then it’s only a matter of time before
we allow nonvoluntary euthanasia, involuntary euthanasia
Brock re
the slippery slope
•
This scenario is possible, but
is it likely?
–
No evidence (speculation)
–
Also, can put safeguards in
place to prevent descent down the slippery slope
Brock’s
recommended safeguards
•
Patient should be given all
relevant information
•
All reasonable alternatives
must be explained
•
There should be a psychiatric
evaluation to rule out depression
•
There should be a waiting
period (to make sure that the request is stable) – and should also make sure it
is truly voluntary (not due to pressure from others)
Nonvoluntary
euthanasia
•
In the case of incompetent
individuals, surrogates make their medical decisions – this might well extend
to the request for euthanasia
•
In some cases, the surrogate
expresses the wishes the patient had when competent
•
In other cases, the patient’s
wishes are unknown – this raises the possibility of abuse
•
Brock – should put better
safeguards in place for all end-of-life decision-making, not just
euthanasia
Callaghan
•
Euthanasia debate represents “three
important turning points in Western thought”
•
Legitimate conditions under
which one person may kill another
•
Meaning and limits of
self-determination
•
Goal of medicine
Four
arguments for euthanasia
•
Moral claim – individual
self-determination
•
Moral irrelevance of
distinction between killing and letting die
•
Lack of evidence for bad
consequences
•
Compatibility of euthanasia
and medical practice
Euthanasia
as a social decision
•
Not just self-determination
because the physician must also make a decision
–
Where does the physician’s
moral right to kill come from? Can we
waive our right to life?
•
In order to be a responsible
moral agent, the physician must agree with the patient (i.e. make an
independent judgment) that the patient’s life is not worth living
Killing and
letting die
• Denying this distinction confuses causality and
culpability: stopping treatment is not causing death
– Once
it became possible to (in some circumstances) prevent death, society
established moral rules governing physician’s obligations in these
circumstances
–
When a physician stops treatment, the disease is the cause
of death “and we have agreed to consider actions like that to be morally
licit”