Bacon Boyle Galileo Hobbes 1 Hobbes 2 Hobbes 3 Descartes  Meditations 1  Meditations 2  Meditations 3a Meditations 3b  Meditations 4 

Meditations 5   Meditations 6a   Meditations 6b   Cartesian Science   Principles I.1-23   Principles I.24-47   Principles I.48-76   Principles II.1-23    

Principles II-IV   Newton 1   Newton 2   Essay I   Essay Sensation   Essay Perception   Essay Substance   Essay Power   Essay Identity      

Essay Abstraction   Essay Knowledge   Essay Existence   Essay Probability   Essay Religion   Bayle 1   Bayle 2   Berkeley0   Berkeley 1   Dialogues Ia

Dialogues Ib   Berkeley Principles  Enquiry IV   Enquiry V.i   Enquiry II-V.ii   Enquiry VI-VII   Enquiry VIII   Enquiry X   Enquiry XII

 

1

Bacon

Preface to The great instauration;

The new organon, Aphorisms 1-46;

selections from The advancement of learning

(Works IV: 13-17, 20-27, 47-57, and 294-98)

 

    1.     What did Bacon mean by comparing the wisdom of the ancients to the boyhood of knowledge?

He took it to be unproductive, just as boys are infertile, but, like boys, to be capable of talking as if it were able to produce something.  What it has failed to produce in particular is an augmentation of knowledge and some means of improving the material conditions of life. (Works IV, p.14)

    2.     How is it that the mechanical arts are superior to philosophy?

They make advances and improve over time. (P.14)

    3.     How did Bacon respond to the charge that the works of the ancients have withstood the test of time, and that if more could have been done to improve the sciences it would have been done already?

He offered two replies.  He observed that knowledge of past discoveries might have been lost, or that the discoveries might have been made by private individuals who never made their knowledge public.  Further supporting this second possibility, he claimed what tends to pass the test of time is not what is most true and useful, but what gives rise to controversy and disputation or what is merely entertaining. (P.15)

    4.     How did Bacon respond to the charge that the pursuit of knowledge of nature may be impious and contrary to divine commands?

By citing the myth of the Garden of Eden and claiming it is rather the pursuit of moral knowledge that was originally forbidden by God, not the identification and classification of the phenomena of nature (symbolized by Adam’s naming of the beasts). (P.20)

    5.     What are the true ends of knowledge?

Not pleasure of contemplation, profit, fame, or power (over other human beings), but “the benefit and use of life.”  This involves a kind of power, but it is power over nature rather than civil power. (P.21)

    6.     What was the chief effect Bacon took the new science he was proposing to promise?

To be able to command nature in action. (P.24)

    7.     What is the proper method to pursue when inquiring into the nature of things?

Induction from particular experience, reaching general concepts and laws only at the end of a long process of investigation.  This is to be contrasted with the method of making a hasty induction to general concepts and principles and then deducing effects from them by syllogistic logic. (P.24)

    8.     How does the type of induction Bacon recommended differ from traditional forms of induction?

Rather than proceed by “simple enumeration,” it will proceed by analyzing experience through a process of exclusion and rejection (i.e., controlled experiment). (P.25)

    9.     What is the key to rectifying the defects of sense experience, according to Bacon?

Using sense just to judge the outcome of properly designed experiments. (P.26)

10.     What is the "fixed and established maxim" that we must not forget on pain of being seduced by the insidious action of ineradicable idols?

That we can only make judgments on the basis of a legitimate induction. (P.27)

11.     What is the most we can do to “effect works?”

Mix or separate substances.  We cannot produce, prevent, or control the reactions that follow as a consequence. (Aphorism 4)

12.     What would Bacon say about the principle that nature always employs the simplest means?

He would call it an idol of the tribe (Aphorism 45, cf. aphorisms 10, 21, 24).  We assume that nature must be a certain way simply because it is easier for our minds to grasp it if it is that way, not because we actually find it to be that way (in fact, we find all sorts of complexities which we seek to explain away and wrongly try to reduce to unity).

13.     What is being joined or separated in the cases where mixing or separation (moving things about) brings about an “artificial” object or occurrence?

Actives and passives. (P. 294)  That is, things with corresponding active and passive powers.  Humans only have the power to move things around.  It is the things themselves that have the power to react — a power we cannot control.

 

2

Boyle

“On the Excellency and Grounds of the Corpuscular or Mechanical Philosophy”

(Matthews, 109-118)

 

    1.     In what way is Boyle’s corpuscularianism unlike the atomism of Epicurus and Lucretius?

Boyle was unwilling to suppose that the universe evolved simply through the atoms having chanced to come together in the right combinations.  (As he pointed out at Matthews, 111, this is what Epicurus and Lucretius thought.)  He thought that God’s intervention is necessary to bring this about.

    2.     What is the cause of all change in the created world, according to Boyle?

Mechanical operations among the parts of matter (bottom of p.111).

    3.     What are the two grand principles of the corpuscular or mechanical philosophy?

Matter and motion (p.113).

    4.     What are the possible effects of one part of matter on another as Boyle envisioned them?

One part of matter can impart motion to another (“drive it on in its entire bulk” — p.113), i.e. it can push or pull it, or it can split it to pieces.  In both cases the effect is a result of collision, which emerges as the only possible cause of change in the created world.  Cf. 117: “One part of matter can act upon another only by virtue of local motion, or the effects and consequence thereof.”  Note, however, that Boyle appears to have allowed that motion might be generated not just by matter (where one part of already moving matter collides with another), but also directly by spirits (cf. 113, 118).

    5.     What are the properties of the parts of matter?

Shape, size, motion, orientation, manner of aggregation of component parts (Boyle actually lists motion, figure, size, posture, rest, order or texture — p.113).

    6.     How many different kinds of matter are there, for Boyle?

In one sense there are infinitely many different kinds of material, because the shapes, sizes, arrangements, and motions of the particles that compose things may be varied in infinitely many ways.  But in another sense, there is just one kind of material because the particles themselves are all cut from the same kind of stuff, so that only the sizes and shapes of pieces makes the pieces different from one another, not anything else like weight or mass or hardness, etc. (pp. 113-114)

    7.     Why did Boyle consider the fact that the parts of matter may be infinitely varied in motion and shape to be an advantage?

It allows for sufficiently rich explanatory resources to deal with almost any phenomenon.  His idea seems to be that the more shapes and motions you have to appeal to, and the more different kinds of compounds of shaped and moving parts, the greater the number of results you can account for as following as a consequence.  This is fine up to a point, but wildly optimistic if you consider that Boyle proposed to explain not just the workings of machines but all physical, chemical, and biological phenomena in this way: electricity and magnetism, fire, emission and absorption of light, brittleness, fluidity, colour, the phenomena of life. (p.114)

    8.     What is wrong with supposing that mechanical principles apply only to medium sized or large objects (like clocks or heavenly bodies) but not to the small parts of things?

All our experience goes to show us that, as bodies are divided down into smaller and smaller parts, mechanical principles still continue to be valid for describing their behaviour — they still operate under the force of pushes and pulls. (pp. 114-15)

    9.     Why did Boyle consider that the principles and explanations of the mechanical philosophy are more satisfying than those of the Aristotelians or other chemists?

Discussion question on p.116.  Broadly, because the mechanical philosophy deals with common notions of everyday life that everyone can understand and experiences regularly, and also that everyone can know how to tinker with.  Everyone understands what it is for one thing to hit one another and the other to move or break up or send the first flying back as a result.  Everyone understands nailing and knitting.  Everyone understands how levers work or ball bearings behave or how axles and spindles and gears and cogs and chains may work in a machine.  All that is involved here is parts of matter hitting other parts of matter and causing them to move.  And because these sorts of causes are so easy to describe and understand, they are also open to us to tinker with, modify and control.  But the principles of the Aristotelian philosophy: form and matter, final cause, act and potency, are very obscure and difficult to understand.  And explanations involving these terms leave no real room for us to modify or control the process of nature.  They leave the ultimate causes of change mysterious or occult and so beyond our control.

10.     What is required for one part of matter to be able to act upon another?

The one has to move and collide with the other (p.117).  But note again that he seems to allow that spirits (as opposed to parts of matter) might have an ability to also initiate motion (cf. 113, 118).

11.     In what sense may the mechanical philosophy coexist with the supposition that change in nature is brought about by the agency of spirits?

Boyle was happy to allow that spirits may exist and act in nature, but he insisted that if they do they must do so by making bits of matter move and collide.  So the principles of mechanical philosophy, far from being undermined by the postulate that spirits act in nature, are themselves necessary to explain the manner in which the activity of those spirits brings about changes in nature.  (The best way to explain Boyle’s willingness to allow for the activity of spirits is to note that he explicitly allowed that motion may be produced, not just as a result of collision of one body against another, but directly by the action of spirits — cf. pp. 113, 118.  So spirits can somehow act on bits of matter to initiate or change the direction of motion.  It is just that all the subsequent effects of this action are described by mechanical principles.)

 

3

Galileo, “Il Saggiatore” (The Assayer)

(Matthews, 53-61)

 

    1.     What is heat generally believed to be?

P. 56.  Something that actually exists as such in the bodies that affect us with the sensation of heat.  When we feel a hot body we get a peculiar warm or burning sensation in our skin.  That is what we commonly call “heat.”  And we suppose that this very thing — this warm or burning feeling isn’t just in our skin but actually inheres in the hot body as a quality.

    2.     According to Galileo there are some properties that it is impossible to conceive a body not having.  What are these properties?

P. 56.  Extension, shape, size, position, motion or rest, contact or separation with other bodies, and number.

    3.     What is the basis for our belief that bodies have such properties as being red or white, bitter or sweet?

Sense experience. P.56

    4.     How could a body possibly have shape but no colour?

All bodies lack colour in the dark. (Applying the claim on pp.57 and 59 that these qualities need not be supposed to exist in the absence of any perceiver.  Darkness removes the conditions under which a perceiver can sense visually and so destroys colour, but the body remains.)

    5.     What significance did Galileo attach to the fact that a body tickles more under the nose than on the back?

He took it to indicate that the tickling sensation must be entirely in us and not in the object. P.57

    6.     What determines whether our tactile sensations will be pleasant or unpleasant?

The configuration of the bodies that touch us. P.58

    7.     What is the cause of variations in taste?

Variations in the arrangement of differently shaped particles. P.58

    8.     What excites tastes, sounds, and odours?

The size, shape, and motion of the bodies that impact on the sense organs.  P.59

    9.     What accounts for the operation of fire?

The quick motion and piercing shape of certain particles in the hot material. P60

10.     Is it right to say that fire is hot, i.e., that heat exists in fire?

It is wrong.  Fires are not hot.  They are only more or less quickly moving.  The only thing that actually exists in fire is motion of its shaped parts.  The heat is a sensation that exists in the person who perceives the fire rather than in the fire itself. (P.60)

11.     Why did Galileo think that a bellows increases the heat of a fire?

P. 60.  Galileo thought that fire is simply a collection of fast moving, very small, sharp particles.  The blast of air from the bellows increases the speed of their motion, which makes them penetrate our body more deeply, do more damage to it as a result, and so give us a feeling of greater heat.  So whereas we today think that the bellows makes the fire hotter because it supplies more oxygen for the chemical reaction that generates the heat, Galileo thought that it makes the fire hotter because it increases the speed of motion of the fire particles.

12.     Did Galileo think that matter is infinitely divisible (i.e., that you can in principle go on dividing a piece of matter in halves forever)?

P. 61.  He thought that the process of division or dissolution can only go up to a point, at which point “truly indivisible atoms” are arrived at.

 

4

Hobbes, Human nature I-III

(Gaskin, 21-30)

 

    1.     What is sense?

A conception produced by the presently occuring action of an object (HN II.2).  There is a fuller definition to be found in De Corp. XXV.2.  Hobbes there specified that sense is the outward rebound of a motion into the sense organ produced by an object.  This is a more strictly physiological account of sense, echoed by what he said later in HN II.8.

    2.     What is colour, and where is it to be found?

The way the motion transmitted by the object into the brain appears to us (HN II.4.3).  It is not clear where it is to be found since it is not obvious where appearances exist.  What exists in the brain is a motion and not an appearance and Hobbes was not friendly to the notion that our minds are distinct from our brains.  So it is not as if brain motions could “appear” coloured to some mind that is looking at what is happening in the brain.

    3.     What convinced Hobbes that colours and images do not exist outside of us?

The facts i) that they are not located in the places where they appear to be located, as is evident in the case of reflections and echos, ii) that we may experience them when there is obviously no external object outside of us causing them, as is evident in the case of double vision, and iii) that we may experience them merely as a result of motion and impact on our sense organs, when once again there is obviously nothing outside of us that could have them, as is evident in the case of seeing a flash of light when one’s head is hit (HN II.5-7).

    4.     What leads us to mistakenly believe that light and sound are outside of us?

The fact that the motion in the brain, which is what these sensations really are, is traveling in an outward direction after having rebounded from going inwards (HN II.8).

    5.     Why do our sensations remain with us after the bodies causing them have ceased to press on our organs, and why do they only slowly fade away?

Because sensation is just a motion of parts within our bodies, and once a thing is set in motion it will continue in that motion unless something special happens to bring it to rest.  Since, even when something does happen to bring what is in motion to rest, it will only be able to do so gradually, and will not be able to stop the motion all at once, it follows that once we do get a sensation it will only fade away gradually (HN III.1).

    6.     If our sensations stay with us after the bodies causing them have ceased to press on our organs, why are we not aware of them?

They are obscured by the more violent motions coming in from the sense organs (HN III.1).

    7.     What is the cause of dreams?

The fact that the sense organs have temporarily ceased to function, so that old motions, left over from past experiences, can come to our attention (HN III.2).

    8.     How did Hobbes define the notions of obscurity and clarity of conception?

Representations are clear when all their parts are distinctly conceivable, obscure when, even though the representation is present as a whole, its parts cannot be distinctly represented or told apart from one another (HN III.7).

    9.     How does remembrance differ from sensing?

When we remember we have an image that has parts that we were previously able to distinctly conceive, but that are now confused, so that we find that the image is able to give less information than we had expected to get from it (HN III.7).

 

5

Hobbes, Human nature IV-VI

(Gaskin, 31-43)

 

    1.     What is the chief reason why, in our deliberations we most often trace out chains of cause and effect, rather than proceed from anything to anything?

There are two parts to the answer to this question: the influence of past experience and appetite.  The influence of past experience explains why one conception follows another in the order in which they do.  Appetite explains why the first conception in the sequence arises in the mind.  On the first point, Hobbes wrote that “the cause of the coherence or consequence of one conception to another, is their first coherence, or consequence at the time when they were produced by sense” (HN IV.2).  That is, the reason why one conception follows upon the other in the order they do is that they were originally experienced in that order.  This is particularly the case with causes and effects.  If one thing causes another, then in sensory experience the conception of the cause will regularly be followed by a conception of the effect and so they will tend afterwards to be imagined in that order.  Thus, Hobbes wrote, “as to the sense the conception of cause and effect succeed one another; so may they after sense in the imagination” (HN IV.2).  Because conceptions tend to follow one another from cause to effect or effect to cause, when someone’s appetites lead them to have a certain desire or aversion, or to conceive a certain end or purpose, they will tend to think first of that end, then the means to that end, then the means to that means, and so on.  Thus, we end up tracing out chains of cause and effect in our deliberations.  As Hobbes puts it, “The cause [of our deliberating in this way] is the appetite of them, who, having a conception of the end, have next unto it a conception of the next means to that end [and from thence to the thought of  the next means … etc.].” (HN IV.2)  See also DE CORP. XXV.8.

    2.     What leads us to suppose that certain events will occur in the future or that events that we have not witnessed have occurred in the past?

Having seen one sort of event regularly happen after another sort in the past.  This experience establishes a mental connection between the two types of event so that whenever the antecedent event is seen, we form a conception of the consequent event, even though it has not occurred yet, and whenever the consequent event is seen, we form a conception of the antecedent event and think it must have preceded, even though we did not witness its occurrence. (HN IV.7).

    3.     What is a sign?

In general, a sign is any conception that leads us to think of some conception other than itself.  At HN IV.9 Hobbes noted that when we have experienced one conception to be regularly followed by another, we are led to have the antecedent conception upon witnessing the consequent and vice versa.  Thus, antecedent and consequent events are at least one kind of sign.  The marks discussed in HN V.1, which are also said to lead us to conceive of something else, are another kind of sign.  Note that Hobbes stressed at HN IV.10 that the connection between antecedent and consequent events is merely conjectural and can often fail.  Indeed, people can often be quite mistaken when they deliberate about future and past events on this basis, and they differ from one another in prudence as a result.  If we think of causes as things that are in fact what brings about an effect, then the antecedent event cannot properly be considered to be a cause or the consequent event an effect.  They are simply signs that lead the mind to form conceptions of one another.

    4.     Did Hobbes think that we are in control of the course of our thoughts?

No.  He thought that we cannot simply will to have a certain thought.  Before we can get a thought, we need to have an experience of something that has been connected with that thought in the past and so calls it to mind (HN V.1).

    5.     What is a mark and what purpose does the creation of marks serve?

Something that can be sensed (perhaps just by hearing), that has been regularly associated with a certain conception in the past, and that is set up in a certain place so that when we go back to that place and run into the mark we will, in virtue of its association, be reminded of the conception (HN V.1).  The use of marks is a way of getting around the fact that we are determined to have the thoughts that we do.  By setting up marks we are in effect able to cause ourselves to have certain conceptions on appropriate subsequent occasions, something we could not otherwise do simply by a sheer act of will or deliberate remembrance or attention.

    6.     In what sense are universal names “indefinite?”

The person who uses a universal name does not expect their hearers to conceive of any particular one of the many individuals referred to by that name.  The person who uses a particular name, in contrast, expects us to conceive of a certain individual (HN V.6).

    7.     What remedy is there for the confusion into which language has fallen by the equivocal and unthinking use of terms?

To go back to sense experience and precisely identify those experiences we want each of our terms to pick out (HN V.14)

    8.     List the four things Hobbes identified as being necessary for knowledge.

To have obtained conceptions of things from experience; to have unambiguously named these conceptions; to have constructed true propositions from these names (propositions where the predicate names a class of objects that include the thing named by the subject), and to have drawn correct or rational inferences from these propositions (VI.4)

 

6

Hobbes, Human Nature VII.1-2, XII, XI

(Gaskin, 43-44, 70-73, 64-70)

 

    1.     How is pain defined on Hobbes’ mechanical conception of the workings of the mind?

A motion that hinders the motion of the heart (HN VII.1).

    2.     How are appetite and fear defined?

An appetite is an impulse to move towards a pleasure, a fear an impulse to move away from a pain (HN VII.2).

    3.     Explain the connection between will, appetite, fear, and deliberation.

Deliberation is the process where an appetite gives rise to a conception of a means to satisfy the appetite, but that conception gives rise to fear, that fear gives rise to a conception of a means to avoid the fear that produces another appetite, and so on until some final appetite or fear is reached.  (The process may also start with a fear.)  The final appetite or fear is what we will (HN XII.1).

    4.     When are we said to be at liberty?

For as long as we have the physical capacity or the command of the resources to enable us to either do or not do a thing, and for as long as we continue to be engaged in the process of deliberating about whether to do it or not. (HN XII.1)

    5.     Why did Hobbes say that deliberation takes away liberty?

Deliberation is the process of reaching a decision about whether to do or not do a thing, and once that decision has been reached, we are no longer at liberty to do otherwise, since we have made up our minds.  So long as deliberation is in process, we are at liberty, but once we have made up our minds there is no longer any question of our being able to do otherwise (if there were, then it would mean that we had not made up our minds yet). (HN XII.1)

    6.     When is an action said to be voluntary?

When it follows from the will.  Voluntary actions are those that are caused by our will whereas involuntary ones are those that result from causes that make our bodies move without producing desires or aversions or acting on our wills (HN XII.3).

    7.     If terrorists threaten to kill your loved ones unless you smuggle something for them, and you do smuggle the goods, is your action voluntary?  Explain Hobbes’ reason for answering the question as he does.

It is voluntary because your action was determined by your own last fear (HN XII.3).

    8.     If, due to an innate character flaw, you are quick to anger, are the actions you perform out of anger voluntary?  Explain Hobbes’ reason for answering this question as he does.

They are voluntary because they still proceed from your own last appetite after deliberation.  That the deliberation is hasty or inadequate changes nothing (HN XII.4).

    9.     If you will to perform an action, is your willing voluntary?

No.  Hobbes considers talk of a voluntary or free will to be not just false, but incoherent.  A voluntary action is one that proceeds from the will, that is, from the last appetite or fear to emerge after deliberation.  To speak of the will being voluntary is therefore equivalent to saying that some last appetite or fear arises in us as a consequence of some last appetite or fear.  But this is nonsense.  If the former appetite or fear is “last” then the other cannot be.  The other is just an earlier stage in the deliberative process that leads up to the truly last stage, and the entire chain of appetite and fear is a product of experience and of opinions concerning what unpleasant or pleasant consequences will follow from what causes (HN XII.5).

10.     What can we know about God?

Nothing, other than that God exists (HN XI.2).

11.     Why do people believe that God exists?

By means of a cosmological argument that infers that there must have been a first cause that gave rise to everything that now exists.  God just is the first cause. (HN XI.2)

12.     What is the erroneous and what the true conception of spirits?

A spirit is properly understood to be an extended, shaped body that is colourless and permeable and so not capable of affecting the senses, like air.  It is improperly understood to be an unextended substance, which Hobbes takes to be a contradiction in terms. (HN XI.4)

13.     What does a miracle prove?

It is a sign that a revelation, message or inspiration was given to someone by some spirit, that is, some superhuman agent.  However, it does not prove that the spirit was godly (HN XI.7).

14.     How can we tell whether a revelation, or message, or inspiration that has been given to someone really came from God?

The inspiration needs to be for some good purpose.  In cases where that is not easily determined, it needs to at least be in conformity with the Christian scripture (HN XI.7).

15.     What is the basis for the belief that the Christian scripture is the word of God?

The trust we place in the testimony of others in the Church, who we must know to be honest and discerning (so not liable to be deceived and not willing to deceive others), right back to the first individuals who saw the miracles and received the Christian message (HN XI.9).

16.     How did Hobbes respond to the charge that he had made faith depend on such natural capacities as our ability to discern whether other people are noble and worthy of trust, rather than (as Protestant doctrine would have it) an inspiration, graciously given by God to the elect, that could bring them to accept the scripture in defiance of all reason?

By claiming that not all people are equally discerning of the good qualities and honesty of others, and that those who are were made so by God.  So it comes down to the same thing in the end.  Either way God graciously made some (and not others) so that they are able to receive the message, the remainder having “hardened hearts.”

17.     What side did Hobbes take in the dispute over whether the individual or the Church is to be the ultimate authority in the interpretation of scripture?

He vests authority in the Church for all but the most important questions.  This follows if our faith in the authenticity of the Bible needs to be derived from the trust we repose in others in the first place (HN XI.10).  Not surprisingly, this echoes his political views, which demand obedience to authority in all but the most important questions (those of life and death).

 

7

Descartes, Discourse on method I-II and V

(AT VI 1-22 and 55-60)

 

    1.     From what does the diversity of our opinions arise?

The fact that we do not all employ the same method, or, as he put it, that “we lead our thoughts along different paths.” (AT VI, 2)

    2.     What are the sciences of mathematics and philosophy good for?

Mathematics for improving the material conditions of life (“facilitating all the arts and lessening men’s labour”); philosophy for indulging in pretentious disputation about matters you do not really understand (“speaking plausibly about all things and making oneself admired by the less learned”). (6)

    3.     What was the chief cause of Descartes’ delight with mathematics and his dismay with philosophy?

He was delighted with mathematics because its claims are certain and evident (7) and disgusted with philosophy because it makes no claims that are not contentious and so open to doubt. (8)

    4.     After abandoning the study of letters, what two sources did Descartes turn to in the search for knowledge?

Both come down to the same thing: experience.  Experience, on the one hand, of the world around him, and on the other of his own nature. (9)

    5.     What led him to subsequently reject one of these two sources as well?

He rejected worldly experience because the things it taught him are not universally accepted in all parts of the world and so are as contentious and dubious as the claims of philosophy. (10)

    6.     What excuse did he offer for proposing an innovation in scientific method, despite the danger that it might be perceived as reformist?

He appealed to a sceptical impasse arising from “the differences that have always existed among the opinions of the most learned,” leaving him uncertain what to believe unless he proceeded on his own initiative.  Because all established knowledge had been called into question by one group or other and so was contentious and dubious, and because no common practice was universally accepted, someone wishing to determine the truth would have no alternative but to seek for a better method, immune to sceptical attack. (16)

    7.     What are the disciplines that Descartes thought most likely to be able to contribute to his plan?

Logic, geometry, and algebra. (17)

    8.     In what way does geometry serve as a model for all the things that can fall within human knowledge?

As in geometry, all are supposed to follow from one another by chains of simple and easy reasoning, proceeding from evidently true first principles and following the rules of proper demonstration. (19)

    9.     Why was it so important to Descartes that he begin his investigations with absolutely certain and indubitable truths?  (This is the first of his four rules of method).

This is not obvious from the text.  But anyone who wants to follow the example of geometricians and mathematicians and proceed to gain knowledge by deducing it from axioms had better be very sure that their axioms are sound.  If you start off with false axioms, everything you deduce from them will be called into doubt.  It is especially important that you be sure of the truth of your initial assumptions if you are going to doubt and reject the evidence of your senses.  People who trust their senses can afford to make mistakes early on, because if they do, the progress of their sensory experiences will soon reveal to them that their deductions are at variance with the way the world is (as Descartes had noted earlier, 9-10).  But if you doubt what the senses tell you, there is no way you can discover your error from subsequent experience.

10.     Could we distinguish between machines that have been perfectly made to look and behave like animals and real animals?

No.  (56)

11.     What are the means by which we can distinguish between machines that look like human beings and real human beings?

By reference to the way they use language to not merely give programmed replies, but respond appropriately to the sense of whatever might be said to them (56), and by reference to their abilities to solve new problems in new ways (57).  The performance of both tasks requires, in Descartes’s view, reasoning abilities that cannot be accounted for as the effects of mechanism since a machine can only do what it was designed to do and cannot respond appropriately to novel circumstances.

 

8

Descartes, Meditations I

 

    1.     What did Descartes take to be required if one is to establish anything “firm and lasting in the sciences,” and why did he think that such drastic measures are required?

We must reject everything we previously thought we knew and start again entirely afresh at building up a new system of knowledge.  Descartes thought this is necessary because he discovered that so many of the things he was taught in his youth were false, and so many other beliefs were based on these false things that almost the whole edifice of his knowledge was so rotten and unstable that there was no other way to fix it than by tearing it all down and starting again. (AT VII 17)

    2.     What would justify rejecting an opinion?

It is not necessary to prove that it is false.  Neither is it necessary to find some reason for doubting it or thinking it is not certain.  All that needs to be done is show that it is founded on something that is open to doubt. (18)

    3.     What was the foundation on which, up to the time of his meditations, Descartes claimed he had based most of his beliefs?

Sense experience (18).

    4.     When have the senses been thought reliable and when unreliable?

They are unreliable only when telling us of small and distant things, but seem reliable when telling us of ourselves and objects in our immediate surroundings, though, as it turns out, Descartes thinks that there is a reason (the fact that we might be dreaming) that ought to lead us to doubt their veracity even then. (18-19)

    5.     Are there any definite signs to distinguish being awake from being asleep according to Descartes?

No. (19)

    6.     If there were no definite signs to distinguish waking from dreaming, what would that prove?

That none of the objects our senses appear to tell us about, including our own bodies, might actually exist. (19)

    7.     Even if there were no definite signs to distinguish waking from dreaming, would there still be certain things our senses tell us about that are not cast into doubt?  If not why not, if so what would these things be?

Descartes suggested that the dreaming argument can only lead us to doubt whether there are compound things around us like the objects our senses reveal to us.  But he thought that the “simple and universal things” that our sensory experiences are composed of, like colours and shapes, ought to correspond to something real, otherwise it would be difficult to explain how we could come to think of these things.  He also thought that there are certain truths we discover upon comparing these simple and universal things with one another, notably the truths of arithmetic concerning numbers of these things, and the truths of geometry concerning shapes, that would have to be true even in a dream. (19-20)

    8.     What did Descartes include in the class of “simple and universal things” from which everything we imagine is constructed?

What he called “corporeal nature in general,” i.e., whatever generally and necessarily goes into everything that is called a body.  More specifically, this means being extended in space.  More specifically yet, it includes shape, size, number, place, and duration. (20)

    9.     In what respect do the sciences of physics, astronomy and medicine all differ from those of arithmetic and geometry?

In two respects: first, the former deal with composite things (i.e., things made up of a number of simple natures), whereas the latter deal only with simple things (e.g. mathematics just deals with number, and different branches of geometry deal with shape, measurement, analysis situs, etc.).  Second, the former make claims about what actually exists in the world, whereas the latter describe their objects without supposing that they actually exist. (20)

10.     Why did Descartes think that even the truths of arithmetic and geometry are open to suspicion of possibly being false?

For two reasons.  Firstly, because he saw no reason to rule out the possibility that someone might be deceiving him or forcing him to deceive himself every time that he performs the proofs of these truths.  Secondly, because people sometimes make mistakes in calculation, even though they know better.  If they make these mistakes sometimes, why could it not be at least possible that everyone might make them all the time? (21)

11.     Why did Descartes think that it would be even more likely that I would always be deceived when performing calculations if God does not exist than if God does exist?

Because if God does not exist, then the cause of my existing would have to be something less perfect than God (God being by definition the most perfect being possible).  But if I had a less than perfect cause, then it is even more likely that there would be some fault in my make-up that would lead me to always perform calculations incorrectly. (21)

12.     What would be wrong with admitting that the existence of my own body, of the world around me, and of the truths of arithmetic and geometry is highly probable?

It might make us slip into treating them as being certain and using them as first principles (22).

 

9

Descartes, Meditations II

 

      1.     What is Descartes’s reason for rejecting the claim that God or some other great being might instill all his thoughts in him?

He noted that for all he knew he might himself be the cause of these ideas.  This seems to be what happens in dreams, for example.  We create all the thoughts ourselves, even though we are not aware that we are doing so. (AT VII 24)

      2.     Why did Descartes think that each of the following reasons for denying that he exists is inadequate:

                           i.     I have denied that I have senses or a body

                         ii.     I have persuaded myself that nothing at all exists in the world

                       iii.     There could be a deceiver who is deceiving me about this

He noted that he had no reason to believe that he needed to have senses or a body in order to exist, (ii) he noted that if he had persuaded himself of something, then he must exist in order to have been persuaded, (iii) he noted that if he was deceived, then he had to exist in order to be deceived. (24-25)

      3.     Why did Descartes reject the traditional view that he is a rational animal?

He found the terminology obscure and meaningless, and thought that clarifying it would be so long and difficult a task that it would not be worth the effort. (25-26)

      4.     Why did he reject the “spontaneous and natural” view that he is a body animated by natural spirits?

Because an evil genius could be deceiving him about the existence of all of these things, and because he had no grounds to be certain that any spatially extended bodies exist. (AT VIII 26-27 and 28)

      5.     What is there that Descartes found to be inseparable from himself?

The act of thinking. (27)

      6.     Would Descartes accept that one ceases to think while in a deep sleep?

He worried that ceasing to think might entail ceasing to exist at p.27.  This is an indication of just how essential he viewed thinking to be to his nature.

      7.     What are the sorts of things that are involved with thinking and that are in Descartes insofar as he is a thinking thing?

Doubting, understanding, affirming, denying, willing, imagining and sensing. (28-29)

      8.     What is there that cannot be false in sensing and imagining?

The things that are being sensed or imagined may not exist, but the act of sensing or imagining must exist in us insofar as these ideas are being had by us.  For, even an evil genius could not deceive us into thinking we are sensing or imagining without actually making us sense or imagine. (28)

      9.     What is there that is really essential to a sensible body like a piece of wax after we remove everything that has to do merely with  the way it manifests itself on special occasions and concentrate just on those features it must always possess in any circumstance whatsoever?

That it is extended somehow in space, capable of taking on a variety of shapes and sizes, and capable of taking on a variety of sensible qualities. (30-31)

  10.     How do these features of the wax come to be known?

Through perception on the part of the mind alone.  That is, through a kind of understanding.

  11.     How do the features that Descartes originally perceived the wax to have come to be known?

In the same way, through an inspection on the part of the mind alone, though this inspection is more obscure and confused.  Descartes stressed at p.31 that it only seems that perception is a sensing or touching or imagining.  In fact, it is always a kind of judging or purely mental apprehension, not involving corporeal sense organs.

 

10

Descartes, Meditations IIIa

(AT VII 34-42)

 

    1.     What made Descartes so sure that nothing we very clearly and distinctly perceives could be false?

My certainty of my own existence is founded on nothing other than a clear and distinct perception.  If such a perception could deceive me, I would not be able to trust it when it tells me that I exist.  Since, however, my own existence is beyond doubt, I must be able to trust it, and so must be able to trust whatever I perceive at least as clearly and distinctly as I perceive my own existence. (AT VII 35)

    2.     Is the existence of the earth, sky, and stars clearly and distinctly perceived?  If not, why not, if so, in what sense?

All that is clearly and distinctly perceived is that my ideas of these things exist in me; I do not clearly and distinctly perceive the existence of external objects resembling these ideas.  This is because the dreaming argument leaves me with a sense of doubt about them. (35)

    3.     Are the truths of mathematics clearly and distinctly perceived?  If not, why not, if so in what sense?

They are clearly and distinctly perceived.  If they are open to doubt, it is only because of a very tenuous and metaphysical ground for doubting them: the thought that God might be powerful enough to deceive us even about things we clearly and distinctly perceive.  This thought enables us to doubt them when we are not engaged in perceiving them (e.g., when we later remember having perceived them but do not review them in all their evidence).  But while we are engaged in perceiving them, we cannot consider the doubt to be at all well founded. (36)

    4.     What is the proper definition of the term, “idea?”

An idea is a thought that is like an image of a thing.  More precisely, it is a thought that is about something else or that refers to an object. (37)

    5.     What is the most frequently occurring error in judgment, in Descartes’s opinion?

Supposing that our ideas depict objects that actually exist outside of us, and depict them accurately. (37)

    6.     Explain Descartes’s distinction between natural impulse and light of nature.

By natural impulse he means a kind of instinct to believe a certain thing, even though we do not clearly and distinctly perceive its truth.  By seeing something in the light of nature, he means clear and distinct perception.  Natural impulse is not a trustworthy source of truth, but it is hard to accept that we might ever be mistaken about what we perceive very clearly and distinctly. (38-39)

    7.     Why is it an error to suppose that because I have some ideas that come and go independently of my will, that therefore these ideas must be caused by external objects?

Because I only know it on the basis of a natural impulse and those sorts of impulses have misled me in the past, and because there could be something else in me aside from my will that brings them about.  This is obviously what happens in the case of dreaming, for instance.  Moreover, we know for a fact that certain ideas that seem to us to proceed from objects do not do so.  For example, there is no bright object about a foot in diameter that hangs just above the clouds and illuminates the earth.  Even supposing there is a sun, it is represented by a very different idea.(39)

    8.     Explain Descartes’s distinction between formal and objective reality.

Formal reality is the collection of real, positive qualities that go to constitute the form of a thing.  Objective reality is the collection of real, positive qualities that go to constitute the form of the object of an idea. (40)

    9.     Why could an effect not be greater than its cause?

Because an effect can only acquire its positive and real qualities (those that make it as great a thing as it is) from its “total” cause (i.e. the totality of the circumstances that work together to produce the effect), and a cause cannot give positive and real qualities to an effect unless it has those qualities to give.  (Note that Descartes did not make these claims positively and in his own voice, but instead tried to prod his readers to accept them by asking rhetorical questions.  Asking questions can sometimes be a way of stating what problem needs to be studied next.  But at other times, as here, it serves as a belligerent way of making a point — by shifting the onus onto the reader to provide reasons to disagree rather than taking on the onus of supplying an argument to convince the reader.  When someone turns to make a point by way of asking questions, it is a fairly clear indication that they lack a good argument for their position.  Those who have good arguments give those arguments.  They do not need to resort to rhetoric.) (40)

10.     Can an idea of an object be more perfect than the object itself?

It can’t.  The idea is like a photocopy or print of an original.  It can be more confused or obscure than the original, but not more perfect in the sense of containing more than is to be found in the original. (42)

 

11

Descartes, Meditations IIIb

(AT VII 42-52, cf. Discourse IV, AT VI 33-36)

 

    1.     What are the three main types of ideas from which all other types of ideas may be formed?

Ideas of myself, of physical bodies, and of God.  Combining aspects of my ideas of myself with my ideas of corporeal things will permit me to form ideas of animals and other human beings, and combining aspects of my idea of myself with my ideas of God will permit me to form ideas of all other sorts of spirits. (AT VII 43)

    2.     What would justify our considering an idea to be false?

Arising in us due to some imperfection in our nature in virtue of which we represented the absence of some type of quality (like heat) as if it were itself a real, positive thing.  If cold is merely the absence of heat, but it nonetheless feels like something to be cold (and not like nothing at all), then cold would be a materially false idea. (43-44)

    3.     How did Descartes define the term “substance?”

It is a thing that can exist on its own, independently of anything else (at least for a time). (44)

    4.     Why did Descartes think that even his ideas of the extension of corporeal things could have been invented by him on his own?

As a substance that is capable of existing on its own, I am greater than extension and its modes, which are mere properties that can only exist within some substance or other.  Descartes claimed this is a sufficient reason for considering me to be the eminent cause of these ideas.  (An eminent cause is a cause that does not formally contain its effect, but that rather belongs to a higher order of being than its effect.) (45)

    5.     What is the particular feature of the idea of God that Descartes found it impossible to explain as an effect of his own nature?

God’s infinity. (45)

    6.     Why should I think that my perception of God is prior to my perception of myself?

Because I conceive of myself as imperfect.  Descartes maintained that an awareness of imperfection is only possible if you have a sense of something more perfect.  So from the fact that we conceive of ourselves as imperfect it follows that we must have a conception of a being more perfect than we are. (45-46)

    7.     Why could I not have created myself?

Because were I powerful and resourceful enough to do that, I should have been powerful and resourceful enough to give myself some better cognitive capacities so that I would not have so many doubts or make so many mistakes.  This is because just bringing a substance (such as myself) into existence out of nothing is more difficult than bringing a quality (such as a power of knowledge) into being.  To bring a substance into being is to create something that can exist on its own, whereas to bring a quality into being is to create something that can only exist in something else.  So anyone who could do the former ought to be capable of doing the latter (48)

    8.     Why does conservation not differ from creation?

Because when the present becomes past, what exists at the present gets destroyed (since the past does not any longer exist).  So to conserve something in existence means constantly recreating it from one moment to the next. (49)

    9.     Why could a chain of human ancestors stretching back to infinity not have produced me?

Because a cause is not just required to account for my first coming into existence but of my being sustained in existence from one moment to the next.  Whatever that cause is, it must be capable of recreating me (a substance) from one moment to the next.  If it was not similarly capable of recreating itself from one moment to the next, it would require some other cause to sustain it.  But there cannot be an infinite regress here, especially because we are concerned with what now sustains me.  (Descartes did not go into any further detail, but perhaps his thought was that it takes time for a cause to act, so that were there even a short chain of causes, I would pass out of existence during the time it takes for a more remote cause, A, to act to sustain a more proximate cause, B, leaving B no more opportunity to act to sustain me, since I’ve disappeared.  It is interesting that Descartes felt it necessary to add this further appeal to sustaining causes.  While many philosophers have considered the claim that there cannot be an infinite regress of past causes for a given effect to be obviously true, others have not been persuaded and the point continues to be debated today.)  But a cause capable of bringing itself into existence would be capable of giving itself all other perfections.  So it would be God. (50)

10.     Why could a number of partially perfect things not have worked together to each contribute a small part of what I find in myself?

Because these would not be adequate to produce my idea of God, which represents all distinct perfections as unified. (50)

 

12

Descartes, Meditations IV

 

    1.     What did Descartes first propose as an answer to the question of what causes me to be deceived and led into error?

Descartes’s first proposal was that error does not arise from anything God made and put into me, but is rather simply due to the fact that I lack something.  So I don’t make mistakes because what God put into me malfunctions, but only because God did not put something into me.  This is a consequence of the fact that I was not created to be a being that possesses all perfections, but instead as a being that occupies an intermediate point on the scale between possessing all perfection (being God) and possessing no perfection (being nothing).  [It might be added by way of further justification that variety in creation is a good thing.  Making a variety of things necessitates making things with varying degrees of perfection ranging between God himself and nothing.  We should praise God for making the universe as rich in variety as it is rather than complain that we are not among the more perfect or angelic forms of creation.]  (AT VII 54)

    2.     Why is this explanation for error “not yet satisfactory?”

Because error does not simply result from something I lack (a privation) but arises from something that ought to be in me.  If I am made to think and judge, as I am, we would expect that God, being a perfect artisan, would make me so that I perform that function correctly.  This is not to say that God could not create imperfect things, but their imperfection would just arise from their not having been created to perform certain functions.  So God could create a thing that just grows and reproduces but does not sense or know and this thing would simply lack perfections.  But given that he creates something that is supposed to sense or know, we should expect that, being an expert artisan, he would have put everything into that thing that it needs to perform those functions well, and so should not have put anything into it that would lead it to be deceived. (55)

    3.     What sorts of causes are utterly useless in physics?  Why?

What Aristotle called final causes, that is, those having to do with the reason why something happens (its end).  Descartes claimed that knowledge of these causes would presuppose knowledge of God’s intentions in making things as they are, and that this is more than we are in a position assume to know, given the vast difference between God and us.  (55)

    4.     What must we be careful to take into account when ascertaining the degree of perfection of a thing?

How well it fits in with the wholes of which it is a part and whether its imperfections might not contribute to a greater perfection in the whole. (55-56)

    5.     On what does error depend?

A capacity of knowing and a capacity of judging or affirming, which involves an act of will. (56)

    6.     What is the proper function of the intellect?

All that the intellect does is perceive ideas (56).  He says that the ideas are ones that I “can” make a judgment about, suggesting that it is not actually the intellect that judges, but the will.  However, as later becomes clear, the intellect can in certain cases compel the will. (59)

    7.     In what sense is the intellect imperfect?

It is imperfect to the extent that it does not clearly or distinctly perceive all the ideas that there are to be perceived. (56)

    8.     Why can we not fault God for creating us with this kind of imperfection in our intellects?

We cannot fault God for making us with intellects that are not able to clearly or distinctly perceive all ideas because this is merely a limitation on what we are able to achieve with our intellects and not a cause of error or imperfection in what our intellects are able to achieve.  Insofar as they simply perceive ideas, they do not judge and do not make mistakes, and insofar as they compel the will to judge, they never compel it wrongly.  They just can’t make judgments about everything.  This is a limitation, not a defect. (56)

    9.     In what does the will solely consist?

An ability to adopt an attitude of affirmation or denial or approval or rejection that does not arise from any external constraint, but merely from our own nature.  Note that Descartes is not here concerned with the freedom of action, but merely with the freedom of willing.  Whether we can act on what we will is another question. (57)

10.     What is the lowest grade of freedom of the will and how does it differ from more perfect grades?

The lowest grade of freedom is when we do not see any reason to prefer one choice over another, and merely pick one.  In higher grades of freedom, there is something in us that determines us to prefer a certain choice.  This thing might either be our understanding or some instinct or insight that God has implanted in us.  The freedom we feel in circumstances of indifference is of a lower grade because it proceeds from an inadequacy in our knowledge. (57-58)

11.     What is the cause of error?

An imbalance between the powers of the will and the intellect, which allows for the possibility that the will might determine us to make a judgment in circumstances where we lack understanding. (58)

12.     How are errors to be avoided?

By using our power of will to refrain from judging unless we feel our will determined to do so by a clear and distinct perception on the part of the understanding. (59)

13.     God could have made me more cautious, so that my caution restrain me from ever willing to affirm something I do not clearly and distinctly understand.  But he didn’t.  Can he be faulted for that?  Why or why not?

Because God may have some inscrutable purpose for allowing this imperfection in my nature. (61)

 

13

Descartes, Meditations V

 

    1.     What qualities did Descartes believe are clearly and distinctly perceived?

Extension in length, breadth, and depth, together with its shapes, sizes, positions and motions, plus various particular geometrical properties and truths concerning these things. (AT VII 63)

    2.     How is it that Descartes could say that my ideas of geometrical shapes are not made by me, even though I can imagine them on my own, and call them up or make them go away at will?

Because they compel me to conceive their content in a certain way (in accord with the laws of geometry) and I have no power to imagine them differently.  For example, cubes can only be imagined to have six faces.  No more than four equidistant points can be imagined. (64)

    3.     How did Descartes respond to the objection that I may have learned of geometrical shapes from sensory experience of similarly shaped objects, and that the reason why I seem to “remember” these shapes rather than to have produced them myself in my own imagination is that I am really just remembering something I have seen before?

He observed that I am able to call up many shapes in my imagination that I am sure I have never seen before, yet these shapes also have geometrical properties that appear to exist independently of my will, and in this sense are more like something I “recollect” than like something I hve myself produced. (64-65)

    4.     Why, according to Descartes, can existence not be separated from the “essence” (i.e., the definition) of God?

Because by definition God is an all-perfect being, and Descartes insisted that existence is a perfection. (65)

    5.     How did Descartes respond to the objection that I might arbitrarily attach the idea of existence to the idea of God in my imagination, so that from the fact that I choose to make this connection, it in no way follows that the connection must be true and that God must exist?

He claimed that it is not up to me whether or not to attach the idea of existence to the idea of God, any more than it is up to me to attach the idea of internal angles equal to two right angles to the idea of a triangle.  The nature of the idea of God itself forces this result, and we have no ability to think otherwise. (66)

    6.     How did Descartes respond to the objection that just because I cannot form an idea of God that does not include the idea of existence, it does not follow that there must be an object (God) that corresponds to this idea?

He admitted that it is generally true that just because things are connected in our ideas, it does not follow that anything exists corresponding to those ideas.  Just because we cannot think of a mountain without a valley (or an up slope without a down slope) it does not follow that a mountain (or a slope) exists.  However, in the case of the idea of God, existence is one of the things that is found to be necessarily connected with the other things that are thought in the idea.  So since it cannot be separated from those other things, any more than an up slope can be separated from a down slope, it follows that those other things, which are characteristic of God, must exist, and hence that God must exist.  My thought of God does not bring this result about, any more than my thought brings it about that a cube must have exactly six faces.  It is instead the nature of the thing itself that brings it about that my thought must exhibit these features. (66-67)

    7.     Supposing that the existence of God is not yet certain, under what circumstances would it be possible to doubt what one has clearly and distinctly perceived?

The circumstance where one is no longer actively engaged in having the clear and distinct perception, but is doing other things and merely recalls having had the clear and distinct perception in the past.  Under these circumstances, the thought that one has often made mistakes in calculation in the past or that there might be an evil genius can induce doubt. (69-70)

    8.     How is it that all demonstrations in mathematics might be said to rest on a prior demonstration of the existence of God?

Because demonstrations in mathematics depend on clear and distinct perception, which, as long as the existence of God is in question, can only be trusted at the time it is actually being experienced.  (Because it is only at that time that the understanding compels the will to believe.)  At other times, when we are not clearly and distinctly perceiving the result, we can doubt it on the grounds that we have made errors in calculation in the past or might be deceived.  However, once the existence of God has been clearly and distinctly perceived, we can say that if the demonstration was in fact clearly and distinctly perceived, then what it tells us is reliable because we cannot be deceived or mistaken about such things.  Thus, a proof of God’s existence provides mathematical demonstrations with evidence they did not previously have. (70)

 

14

Descartes, Meditations VIa

(AT VII 71-80)

 

    1.     What sorts of material things can at least possibly exist?

Those that are the objects of pure mathematics.  Such objects are considered to only have those properties that mathematics deals with: shape, size, motion, and divisibility into a number of parts.  They are not considered as bearing any sensible qualities. (AT VII 71)

    2.     How does imagination differ from understanding?

When we imagine we not only grasp the definition or the simple natures that go into making the thing what it is, but “see the thing as if it were present,” i.e., we make something like a “picture” of the thing. (72)

    3.     Why is imagination not part of my essence?

Essence has to do with what a thing has to have in order to be the sort of thing that it is.  And I can quite well imagine myself still being a thinking thing, and even still having all the thoughts I now have (since imagination merely duplicates some of the thoughts I have in my understanding) without the imagination.  So it can have nothing to do with my essence. (73)

    4.     Why is it not without reason that people think that they sense bodies existing in space outside of them rather than sense only their own thoughts?

Because these ideas occur independently of their wills, and because they are much more vivid, explicit, and detailed than the ideas formed in imagination. (75)

    5.     What sort of things are taught to us by nature?

That we need to flee what causes pain as it is damaging the body, that what is pleasing is beneficial to the body, that particular sensations (such as hunger or thirst) are indicative of a need to perform certain actions (eat or drink), that objects exist in space outside of us and resemble the sensations we receive, that we have bodies to which we are intimately connected so that we can move them and feel pleasure and pain from them. (75-76)

    6.     What allowed Descartes to claim that the fact that I experience a pain in a certain part of my body is not enough to prove that that part exists?

One thing is the dreaming argument of Meditations I, but on 77 he mentions another one: the case of the phantom limb.  People who have had a limb amputated report still experiencing it as if it were there, so obviously a limb need not be present for a pain in that limb to be felt by the mind.

    7.     Why should the fact that I can clearly and distinctly understand one thing without the other entail that they are really different from one another?

Because the ability to clearly and distinctly conceive the one without thinking of the other shows that there would be no impossibility in God bringing the one about without or apart from the other.  And that means that they must really be different things.  God could not bring about a mountain without a valley (since a valley just is what is at the base of a mountain), because these are one and the same thing considered under different descriptions.  But if God can bring about the one without the other, then it is not merely the descriptions that are different, but the things. (78)

    8.     Explain the nature of the relation that Descartes supposed to hold between himself and his powers of sensing and imagining.

He thought that these capacities are not really part of me, but are at best attached to me.  I could exist as a thinking being even if I were to lack them, but they would need to be instantiated in some human being or other in order to exist. (78)

    9.     Why would God be a deceiver if my ideas of extended bodies were not caused by extended bodies?

Because these ideas must have some cause that contains extension either formally or eminently and God gave me a strong inclination to believe that this cause contains extension formally and not eminently.  Since there is no way I could discover the error of this inclination were it mistaken (since it has been established that God could have created material things), and since I can conceive of myself perfectly well without having to think of it, which means it must be really separate from me, God would be a deceiver were he to have given it to me were what it tells me false. (79-80)

 

15

Descartes, Meditations VIb

 

    1.     Why is it that even though Descartes thought he could demonstrate that corporeal things must exist, he still did not think that those things exist exactly as we grasp them by sense?  What must be true of them?

Because what our senses reveal to us is in very many cases obscure and confused.  Corporeal things need only contain what we clearly and distinctly perceive.  As it turns out, this means that they must be extended somehow.  But exactly how they are extended, what particular sizes and shapes and motions they have, or whether they contain anything in addition to extension are not things we clearly or distinctly perceive. (AT VII 80)

    2.     What things did Descartes think are taught to us by nature and what by a habit of making reckless judgments?

By nature we are taught that we have bodies and that our sensations of hunger, thirst, and pain indicate when these bodies are in a less than optimal state.  We are also taught that other bodies exist, that our sensations of different sensible qualities arise from differences in these bodies, and that sensations of pleasure and pain indicate whether these bodies are harmful or beneficial to our bodies.  Reckless judgment teaches us that there is empty space and that bodies have exactly those sensible qualities and those modes of extension that they are peceived to have. (80-82)

    3.     What is the proper purpose for which sensations were given to the mind?

To signify those things that are harmful or beneficial to the continued union of mind and body. (83)

    4.     Did Descartes think that all the motions of our bodies are mechanically caused?

No.  Some are determined by the will and the mind. (84)

    5.     What is necessary if the mind is to be affected by the body?

A particular part of the brain, the common sense, must be affected. (86)

    6.     Does the brain feel pain?

No.  It simply undergoes a motion, transmitted to it by the nerves.  It is the mind that experiences a sensation of pain as a result of certain motions occurring in the brain. (87)

    7.     Why is it in fact better that our senses should occasionally deceive us about what is good or bad for us?

Because it is preferable that they tell us what is good or bad for us in the vast majority of cases than that they not tell us anything at all.  And there is no other way they could work.  They have to communicate what is happening at the surface of the sense organ to the brain.  Since the brain is widely separated from the sense organs, information has to travel along a chain of nerves from the sense organs to the brain.  That creates the possibility of deception when other causes than the usual ones move the nerves or the brain in the same way. (88-89)

    8.     What needs to be done in order to be sure that our senses are not deceiving us?

We need to check the reports that a given sense organ is giving against those supplied by other organs, bring in our memories of what our senses have told us at earlier times about the thing we are examining, and check that all this information is consistent with what our understanding, through clear and distinct perception, tells us could be possible. (89)

    9.     In what does the difference between dreaming and waking experience consist?

Descartes claimed that dreams involve a discontinuity in the sequence of events. (89)

 

8a

Descartes, Principles I.1-23

 

    1.     Why should we think that we are the victims of prejudices or “preconceived opinions” that have kept us from knowledge of the truth?

Because we began life as infants who did not have full reasoning abilities and made infantile judgments about the objects of sensory experience that may not have been rationally justified.  Note that Descartes was not opposing reasoning to sense experience.  His claim was not that as infants we could only rely on sense experience and it deluded us about things whereas reason reveals the truth.  He instead meant to oppose infantile judgment to rational judgment.  His point was that, as infants, we made infantile judgments about the nature of the objects of sensory experience.  These judgments are inconsistent with what reason tells us about those same objects (the objects of sensory experience).  Descartes is not opposing sensible knowledge of a sensible world to rational knowledge of a purely intelligible world, but irrational or pre-rational opinion about the sensible world with rational knowledge of the sensible world. (Princ. I.1)

    2.     What is the “scale” of the doubt that Descartes proposed in Principles I.1?  What things does he propose to call into doubt and what things would he consider to be above doubt?

He proposed to doubt “everything which we find to contain even the smallest suspicion of uncertainty.”  In other words, if you can conceive any reason to doubt something, however extravagant that reason may be, you should doubt it, so that the only things that are immune to doubt are those things that are so obvious and certain that no reason can be offered for thinking they might be otherwise than they are. (Princ. I.1)

    3.     What is called into doubt by the fact that our senses sometimes deceive us and by the fact that there is no certain way of distinguishing being awake from dreaming?

The actual existence of all the objects of sensory experience.  Note that the stress is placed on “existence,” rather than on “object.”  We do not doubt the objects of sensory experience themselves in the sense of doubting that they are what we conceive them to be.  We don’t doubt that a red square is red or is square.  We don’t doubt that we have the concept of a red square or worry that our concept of a red square might be a concept of something entirely different.  We only doubt that it exists where and when it is presented to us, or that what actually exists in the place and at the time where we think a red square exists really is a red square.  (Princ. I.4)

    4.     Should we doubt principles that are revealed to us by reasoning?  If so, why?  If not, why not?

Yes, we should, for two reasons.  One is that we see people around us make mistakes in reasoning and yet be convinced that they are right, which proves that it is possible to be deceived about the results of demonstration.  The other is that we cannot presume that we were so perfectly made that our reasoning powers should perform flawlessly.  Even if our cause was an all-perfect being, it could have made us such that we are always deceived about matters we know by reasoning or demonstration.  After all, since it obviously did make us so that we are deceived about these matters sometimes, this establishes a possibility that it could have made us so that we are deceived about these matters all the time. (Princ. I.5)

    5.     What are the limits of human freedom?

We have no ability to refrain from believing things that are completely certain and that have been thoroughly examined.  (Princ. I.6.  As will be discovered later, this is not actually a limitation, in Descartes’s estimation, but the highest expression of freedom.  So it turns out that there are no limits on human freedom at all.  It is “infinite.”  This will be considered later.)

    6.     What makes my existence certain (beyond all possibility of doubt)?

Because to doubt that I exist is to think and to think is to exist, so I cannot doubt that I exist without providing myself with a certain demonstration that I do in fact exist. (Princ. I.7)

    7.     What am I certain of when I claim to be certain of my own existence?  What else, besides myself, am I certain of insofar as I have this certainty of my own existence?

Just that we have thoughts.  We remain uncertain that anything revealed to us by the senses is true, and so remain uncertain that we have bodies.  My certainty of myself is therefore inseparable from certainty of the existence of certain thoughts, understood as things that “happen within me” and of which I have some awareness.  This means, in effect, that I am certain of the existence of my thoughts or concepts of all the objects of sensory experience, considered as thoughts or concepts in me.  Note that, in speaking in this way, Descartes was implying that we are certain, not just of the thoughts, but of something that “contains” them — something “within” which they occur.  This container for thoughts is myself.  So in being certain that I exist I am certain of the existence of at least two different sorts of things: myself and my thoughts. (Princ. I.9)

    8.     What is “known by the natural light?”

That nothingness has no attributes or qualities. (Princ. I.11.  By the way, this sudden appeal to the “natural light” as a kind of oracle stands in stunning incongruity with what has been said up to now about only accepting what is beyond any shadow of a doubt, particularly when we consider that Descartes meant to employ the contrapositive principle that the existence of attributes or qualities implies the existence of something (some substance) that has those attributes or qualities.  One would have expected some demonstration of this “nothingness principle at least on a level with that provided for certainty of self existence.)

    9.     What determines that there must be some substance in existence?

The presence of attributes and qualities. (Princ. I.11)

10.     What makes our knowledge of a substance “clear”

The greater the number of attributes and qualities we find in a thing, the clearer our knowledge.  (Princ. I.11)

11.     Why do we find more attributes in our minds than in anything else?

Because any attribute or quality we think we find in anything else is experienced by way of some idea we find in ourselves and so indicates the presence of a correspondent attribute or quality of the mind (though, of course, not necessarily the same one). (Princ. I.11)

12.     Where does the power of sense perception reside?

In the mind, not the body.  (Princ. I.12)

13.     What makes it of paramount importance for us to determine what ultimately caused us to exist?

Keeping within the bounds of the doubt articulated over Princ. I.1-6, it is not possible for us to know anything outside of ourselves.  Limiting ourselves to what we find in us, it is possible to identify certain ideas and “common notions” and to attempt to demonstrate truths about these ideas by appeal to the “common notions.”  (This is perhaps already what was done in Princ. I.7 and 11.)  But we cannot be assured of the truth of the results of these demonstrations as long as we think that we may have been so imperfectly designed as to make systematic errors in demonstration — errors that could in principle not be corrected by adopting a correct method and making frequent reviews.  So before we can proceed to demonstrate anything further, we need to establish what designed us and whether it would have made us like that. (Princ. I.13)

14.     Under what conditions is it possible to doubt the results of demonstrations?

When not attending to the sequence of steps involved in the proof, but remarking instead on the history of past errors in proofs of a like nature and the possibility that we may have been designed so as to make systematic errors in demonstration.  However, while attending to the steps of the proof themselves, this is not possible. (Princ. I.13)

15.     What is contained in the idea that the mind finds in itself of God that guarantees that the object of this idea must necessarily and eternally exist?

The concept of supreme perfection.  Though not stated explicitly here, Descartes believed that a being that does not exist would be less perfect than one that does exist, and one that exists only contingently would be less perfect than one that exists necessarily and eternally. (Princ. I.14)

16.     Why must we conclude that the supreme being does exist?

Because we perceive that to be a consequence of what we find contained in our idea of God, in the same way that we perceive having internal angles equal to two right angles to be a consequence of what we find contained in our idea of a triangle. (Princ. I.14)

17.     In what way are ideas different and in what way are they all alike?

They are all alike in being “modes” of thinking (different ways in which the act of thinking is “modified”).  They differ in depicting different things.  (Princ.  I.17)

18.     What is required to give someone the idea of an intricate object?  What assures us that this must be so?

An equally intricate object. (Princ.  I.17)  We are assured of this by the “light of nature” (this is a second reference to the oracular source of knowledge mentioned in I.11), which on this occasion declares that causes must actually contain as much or more than is found in their effects.  In this case, the cause of an idea must contain all the real qualities represented in the idea, or something greater than those qualities. (Princ.  I.18)

19.     How can we have an idea of supreme perfections if we are ourselves imperfect?

Because it was put in us by a supremely perfect being, who must therefore exist. (Princ.  I.18)

20.     Why must the whole world be continually recreated from one moment to the next?

Because whatever presently exists becomes past and what is past no longer exists.  This means that the bare passage of time suffices to destroy everything, and would do so were there not some cause continually recreating it with each passing moment. (Princ. I.21)

 

9a

Descartes, Principles I.24-50

 

    1.     What is the way to acquire the most perfect scientific knowledge?

We are to start from knowledge of God, considered as an all-perfect being and as cause of everything else, and then attempt to deduce from this what sorts of things God would have caused to come to be. (Princ. I.24)

    2.     What things are to be regarded as finite, what things as infinite, and what things as indefinite?

Finite things are those that have some limit.  Indefinite things are things that have no limit so far as we can tell, or things that are such that, for any given limit, they can be imagined to extend beyond it.  Examples are space, time, and the things that occupy space and time.  God alone is to be regarded as infinite, only God is properly known to be without all bounds. (Princ. I.26-27)

    3.     Distinguish between two different ways in which God could be considered as cause of things and give Descartes reasons for asserting that we can only have knowledge of one of these sorts of cause.

Principles I.28 speaks of efficient and final causes.  A final cause is a cause that acts to achieve some purpose.  While God undoubtedly created the universe in order to achieve some purpose, Descartes maintained that we have no knowledge of what that purpose might have been and are therefore in no position to consider God as final cause of the universe.  However, he did think that certain things have been revealed to us about God’s nature that put us in a position to draw conclusions about the manner in which God acts to do things and the general sorts of things that God would act to bring about.  When we do this we consider God just as an “efficient” or prior cause that acts in a law like way on things to modify them, though its reasons for so doing so are not specified.

    4.     What sorts of effects should we consider God to be the cause of, and what sort of effects should we not consider God to be the cause of?

We should consider God to be the cause of those effects that are evident to our senses (the universe and the things in it).  Consistent with the answer to the previous question, we should not be speculating about what goals God might have aimed at achieving in creating these sensible things. (Princ. I.28)

    5.     In what sense is God not the cause of our errors?

The strict and positive sense.  What this means is further explained in Princ. I.31. (Princ. I.29)

    6.     Under what conditions would God deserve to be called a deceiver?

If he gave us a power of knowledge that led us to false beliefs even when we were using it correctly. (Princ. I.30)

    7.     What can we be certain of once we have established the existence of God?

All the truths of mathematics and the other demonstrative sciences, but also everything that is clearly and distinctly apprehended in sensory experience, regardless of whether we are awake or dreaming, so long as we just focus on what is really clearly apprehended in it. (Princ. I.30)

    8.     On what does error depend?

Our will.  (Princ. I.31)  As specified in more detail later (Princ. I.33-35), error arises when we make a judgment about something we have not accurately perceived.  This is something the will gives us power to do.

    9.     Why do errors not require the concurrence of God for their production?

Because they don’t arise from anything God has given to us, but rather from something God has refrained from giving to us.  As Descartes put it, they arise from something negative or privative — something lacking. (Princ. I.31)

10.     Why is God not to be blamed either for not having given us an infinite intellect or for not having limited our powers of will?

God is under no obligation to his creatures to put everything he possibly can into them.  Were that the case God would be restricted to only creating rival gods.  He is likewise only to be praised for giving our wills infinite scope since this is what alone has made us free agents and so beings of a higher order than automatons. (Princ. I.36-37)

11.     How is freedom of the will to be reconciled with divine preordination of all things?

We don’t know.  But this is actually the key to the reconciliation rather than an admission of defeat.  Descartes did propose to explain how to effect such a reconciliation in Princ. I.41, and he meant it.  The reconciliation is effected by saying that while we are sure that God’s power is infinite, and sure as a consequence that he must have forseen and preordained all things, we cannot presume to fully understand this power, precisely because it is infinite and a grasp of infinities is beyond us.  Just as it is beyond us to say whether an infinite number is even or odd, so it is beyond us to say how God’s infinite power is exercised.  This means that something that we very clearly and distinctly perceive, such as our own will, can neither be rejected nor supposed to be inconsistent with divine preordination.  Because the manner of divine preordination is incomprehensible and freedom undeniable, we must accept that freedom is somehow consistent with preordination.

12.     What must we do to avoid error?

Restrict assent only to what we clearly and distinctly perceive.  (Princ. I.43)

13.     How do we know whether or not we have clearly and distinctly perceived something?

If it is really clearly and distinctly perceived, it is beyond your power to refrain from assenting to it.  This is because the understanding determines the will when it perceives clearly and distinctly and only leaves it free to assent or deny when it does not. (Princ. I.43)

14.     What is meant by clear and distinct perception?

To be clearly perceived, a thing must be perceived in such a way that you can tell it apart from other things (by analogy, when a visible object stimulates the eye sufficiently to make it stand out from its surroundings, it is seen clearly).  To be distinctly perceived, a thing must be perceived in such a way that you can tell its parts apart from one another (by analogy, a visible object is seen distinctly when you can not only tell it apart from its surroundings, but tell its parts apart from one another). (Princ. I.45)

15.     Identify two ultimate classes of things and three classes of affections of things.

Thinking things, also called minds or thinking substances, and material things, also called bodies or extended substances.  There are affections of thinking things, which are the various modifications of the acts of willing and perceiving, affections of extended things, which are the various ways extension can be modified (shape, size, position, order, motion), and finally affections arising from the close union of thinking and extended things: appetites, emotions, and sensations. (Princ. I.48)

16.     How is it that eternal truths or common notions might not be clearly conceived by everyone?

Because they have conflicting preconceptions gained from erroneous childhood inferences. (Princ. I.50)

 

10a

Descartes, Principles I.51-76

 

    1.     What is a substance?

A thing that exists independently of anything else. (Princ. I.51)

    2.     In what sense are bodies and created minds substances?

They only depend on God for their existence, not on anything else. (Princ. I.52)

    3.     What is required in order to know a substance?

Experience of one or more of its attributes. (Princ. I.52)

    4.     What is it about thought and extension that makes the one the sole principal attribute of mind and the other the sole principal attribute of body?

All the other attributes of mind are merely modifications of our manner of thinking, and all the other attributes of body are merely modifications of extension.  Though very radical, this claim is here presented without any exposition or defense.  It entails that mass, solidity, hardness, ductility, brittleness, viscosity, salinity, acidity, and many other material qualities, not to mention colour, taste, and heat and cold, are actually only ways in which extension is “modified.” (Princ. I.53)

    5.     What sort of “things” are duration, order, and number?

They are different “modes” or modifications of the existence of substances of any sort. (Princ. I.55)

    6.     From what do universals arise?

The fact that we make use of a single idea to think of all the individuals that resemble one another in some way. (Princ. I.59)

    7.     What is a universal term?

A term used to name ideas of the sort described in the previous answer. (Princ. I.59)

    8.     Distinguish between genus, species, differentia, property, and accident.

A genus is a universal idea (an idea of the sort described in the answer to question 6).  A species is a universal idea that represents just one specific kind of individual thing that is represented by the universal idea.  The differentia is the distinguishing property of the species, the thing that makes it a member of that species rather than of some other that falls under the genus.  Properties are things that follow from the differentia, and therefore are further things that all members of the species must have.  Accidents are things that members of the species may or may not have. (Princ. I.59)

    9.     Distinguish between real, modal, and conceptual distinction.

A real distinction is a distinction between different substances or, in the case of extended substances, between the spatially distinct parts of those substances.  In these cases the things being distinguished can be thought of one independently of the other.  E.g., God apart from anything else, mind apart from body and body apart from mind, and any part of body apart from the surrounding parts.  A modal distinction is either a distinction between a mode and a substance or between two modes of the same substance.  In this case, the mode cannot be conceived apart from the substance it is distinguished from, though the substance can be conceived apart from the mode.  Even where two modes of the same substance are considered, they can be conceived apart from one another, but neither of them can be conceived apart from the common substance they belong to.  (Distinctions between modes of different substances are better regarded as real distinctions.)  Conceptual distinctions are distinctions between substances and their attributes or between attributes of the same substance.  In this case we cannot form a clear idea of the distinguished things in separation from one another. (Princ. I.60-62)

10.     When is the distinction between extension and body conceptual and when is it modal?

It is conceptual when we consider extension as the principal attribute of body, since in this case we cannot clearly conceive the substance, body, without conceiving its attribute.  It is modal when we are considering some specific way in which extension is modified (as of this size or shape or that, in motion or at rest).  In this case we can very well conceive the substance having some other modification instead. (Princ. I.63-64)

11.     What have we taken for certain and indubitable from early childhood?

That bodies existing outside us have qualities that resemble those given in our sensations, and in particular that there is something on the surfaces of bodies that resembles our sensations of colour. (Princ. I.66)

12.     Where does the pain of a stubbed toe exist?

In the mind (not in the toe). (Princ. I.67)

13.     When are pain and colour clearly and distinctly perceived?

When they are regarded merely as sensations or thoughts. (Princ. I.68)

14.     Why are pain and colour not clearly and distinctly perceived when judged to be real things existing outside of the mind?

Because then we have no way of understanding what they are. (Princ. I.68)  (This extraordinary claim is not further justified at this point.  Descartes’s view may have been that we don’t understand how to account for colour and pain as modifications of extension, but that would beg the question of why we should think that extension is the only attribute of body when our senses tell us that it has other attributes as well.  It is not clear why Descartes’s charge that we don’t understand what colour and pain are couldn’t be answered by saying that they are exactly what they appear to be: colours on the surface of bodies, and pains located in bodily organs.  If this is not good enough, then it is not clear why it should be good enough to say that they are sensations existing in minds.  We have no more idea how minds can taken on colours than we do how bodies can take them on.)

15.     What must our judgments of colour be like in order to avoid error?

We must judge that there is something we do not know in whatever things it may turn out to be that affect our senses that causes our sensations of colour. (Princ. I.70)

16.     Do infants see objects as coloured?

No.  They experience all of their sensations only as states of themselves. (Princ. I.71)

17.     What initially led us, as children, to suppose that objects exist outside of us?

Moving around and discovering that the shaped things we perceive do not move with us and so appear to have an external existence. (Princ. I.71)

18.     What initially led us, as children, to attribute our sensations to external objects?

Moving around and discovering that objects with characteristically different shapes seemed to be responsible for causing particular sensations. (Princ. I.71)

19.     On what basis did we originally ascribe reality to objects?

Not on the basis of whether or not they are extended, but with reference to how capable they are of harming or benefiting us. (Princ. I.71)

20.     Identify four main causes of error.

Preconceptions or false judgments formed in childhood; an inability to forget those preconceptions; difficulties in attending to things that cannot be sensed or imagined; and a tendency to use words in place of thinking of what they mean. (Princ. I.71-74)

 

11a

Descartes, Principles II.1-23

 

    1.     Why would God be a deceiver if material things did not exist?

Because we have ideas of them and we also have the idea that these ideas are not the products of our own will but are caused by something that is like what the ideas represent.  Since God is not like these ideas (not being an extended body), he would be deceiving us were he to give them to us or allow anything that is not similar to them to give them to us. (Princ. II.1)

    2.     What do pain and other sensations teach us?

That there is a particular body to which we are closely conjoined, and that some external bodies are beneficial, others harmful to our union with this body. (Princ. II.2-3)

    3.     What is hardness, as far as our senses are concerned?

The sensation of strain we get in our muscles when we try to push or squeeze something and it does not yield. (Princ. II.4.)

    4.     Why does the nature of body not depend on weight, hardness, colour, or other such qualities?

Because it can be conceived to exist without them, from which it follows that it is at least modally distinct from them (so that they are at best “accidents” and not properties or primary attributes).  Descartes would have wanted to go further and maintain that the distinction is real as well as modal. (Princ. II.4)

    5.     Why do preconceived opinions about rarefaction and empty space confuse the truth that the nature of body is just extension?

Because they lead us to suppose that body must be something more than space.  The first leads to this consequence indirectly, by leading us to suppose that the extension can vary while the body remains the same, so that body must be something more than extension, whereas the second leads to it directly, by saying that the one can be separated one from the other and so cannot be the same as it. (Princ. II.5)

    6.     What makes some bodies denser than others?

Their shape.  Rare bodies have pores or holes. (Princ. II.6)

    7.     Why should we think that the extension constituting a body is exactly the same with that constituting a space?

Because we cannot identify anything else that is essential to a body and that it could not exist without. (Princ. II.11)

    8.     What are we thinking of when we think of the extension of the place that a body occupied after it has moved away from that place?

A surface (perhaps defined by the outer surfaces of the immediately surrounding bodies) that has the same size and shape and that is in the same position relative to certain landmark bodies. (Princ. II.12)

    9.     What is the point of Descartes’s example of the man on the ship?

That place is nothing absolute but is merely defined relative to surrounding bodies that we consider to be immobile (though from other points of view they may not be immobile, but something else may be and there may be nothing that is absolutely fixed and that therefore forms an ultimate frame of reference). (Princ. II.13)

10.     Distinguish between internal and external place.

Internal place is the extension of a body, considered as a property of that body that moves around with it wherever it goes.  External place is the surface common, at any point in time, to a body and the bodies that immediately surround it, and considered merely as a mode that any of a number of bodies could indifferently have.  As long as this surface continues to have the same size and shape and to be in the same position relative to landmark bodies considered to be at rest, we consider the external place to the same, even though the body in the place may change, or the body stay where it is and the immediately surrounding bodies change (as with a ship on a river being held in the same place while the wind blows in one direction and the stream flows in the other. (Princ. II.15)

11.     Why can there be no such thing as a vacuum?

Because extension is a property and it is a complete contradiction that there should be any property where there is nothing to have that property.  Consequently, where there is extension there must be body. (Princ. II.16)

12.     Why could even God not remove all body from a vessel while preventing any other body from taking the place those contents had occupied?

Because extension just is body, so where there is extension there must be body.  To remove all body whatsoever from a vessel would be to remove the extension from between the walls of the vessel, that is to cause them to collapse onto one another. (Princ. II.18)

13.     Why can there be no more matter in a vessel filled with lead or gold than in one filled with air?

Because the quantity of matter does not depend on the kind of material or its weight or density but simply on how much space it takes up. (Princ. II.19)

14.     What do Descartes’s claims about space have to do with his argument against the possibility of atoms?  (The title of the article claims that the argument depends on the position on space, but the article itself only talks about what follows from the power of God.)

The argument also depends on the claim that any atom, however small, must be conceived to take up some space.  That is a consequence of the simple identification of space with body that Descartes had been arguing for over the preceding articles.  If it does not take up some space, it just isn’t a body.  But if it does take up space, then it can be conceived to have a right half that is in a different place from its left half and so is divisible, at least by the power of God. (Princ. II.20)

15.     In what sense are all materials (gold, lead, salt, sulphur, mercury, water, air, etc.) identical in kind?  What accounts for all the differences between what are falsely considered to be different kinds of materials?

They are all made of the same thing, namely extension.  The only differences arise from how this extension is cut up into parts, and how these parts are shaped, ordered, and moving.

 

12a

Descartes, Principles II.33-40 and 64; IV.189-199 and 203-4; Discourse VI (AT VI: 63-65)

 

    1.     What relevance does the fact that there can be no vacuum and no rarefaction or condensation (in the sense of a gain or loss of volume by a material that completely fills the space it occupies throughout the change) have for the theory of motion?

It implies that the only motion can be rotation of a “ring” of matter. (Princ. II.33)

    2.     Why must matter be indefinitely divisible?

To make it possible for motion of irregularly sized or shaped rings of matter to occur without creating a vacuum between moving parts or causing rarefaction or condensation.  Since the planets move in ellipses, Descartes had to account for this phenomenon somehow. (Princ. II.34)

    3.     What might the “bodies as wide as the space at E” referred to in article II.35 be?

Planets orbiting around the sun in elliptical orbits.

    4.     What might Descartes be referring to when he speaks in article II.36 of changes (sc. in the quantity of motion in the universe) that we know to take place either by experience or revelation?

Possibly changes produced by the free volitions of human minds to move or halt their bodies.

    5.     Why must the quantity of motion in the universe be preserved?

Because God, being a perfect being, is constant in the way he acts.  For Descartes this means that having once decided to create something, God will preserve that thing in existence.  Why constancy should have to be expressed in this particular way is unclear.  One might be constant by letting the quantity of motion continuously decay, or continuously increase, or continuously oscillate. (Princ. II.36.)

    6.     Is it natural for bodies that have been set in motion to slow down and stop?  What is it that teaches us the answer to this, sense experience or understanding?

No.  We know this by understanding (specifically by a deduction from the constancy of God).  Sense experience teaches us that things naturally tend to rest, but this is only because all the bodies on the earth run into things that slow them down before long. (Princ. II.37)

    7.     What is the result of movements caused in the brain by the nerves?

The soul or mind is affected in different ways, corresponding to the different movements. (Princ. IV.189)  God will have pre-ordained that particular movements will always particular sensations, and will have set things up so that, when the senses are functioning normally, the sensations are ones that impel us to act in ways appropriate to preserve the mind/body union.

    8.     Propose a Cartesian remedy for depression (sadness not caused by any obvious misfortune).

Since Descartes attributed this feeling to a thickening of the blood around the heart, causing nerves from the heart to transmit impulses to the brain that are ordained to cause a feeling of sadness (Princ. IV.190), a remedy would consist in doing something to thin the blood.  Perhaps drinking copious amounts of water.

    9.     What conclusion should be drawn from the fact that people complain of feeling pains in a limb that has been amputated?

That pains do not actually occur in the body parts where we think they are felt, but only in the brain (or mind) where they arise as a consequence of motions transmitted by the nerves (in this case, the stumps of the severed nerves being moved in the same way they were previously moved when the limb was being affected painfully).  Moreover, that the same is the case of all of our sensations, which are likewise felt only as a consequence of motions in the nerves, as may be shown by further experiments of a like nature. (Princ. IV.196-97)

10.     Why should we think that the nerves do not transmit anything but motion to the brain (e.g., that the visual nerves do not transmit colour, the olfactory nerves smell, the tactile nerves heat)?

Because anatomy tells us that the nerves are all alike.  If they served to transmit different qualities, we would expect to find differences between them. (Princ. IV.198)

11.     Where does the feeling of titillation or pain, and the appearance of light and sounds originate?

In the mind.  In the external world and in the body, brain, and nerves there is nothing but parts in motion. (Princ. IV.198)

12.     What makes it unlikely that the colours we sense are produced by colours actually existing on the surfaces of bodies?

If you are struck on the eye in a dark room, you see flashes of light even though there is nothing coloured around you.  This shows that colour is experienced as a consequence of motion in the object affecting the organ, not as a consequence of colour in the object affecting the organ. (Princ. IV.198)

13.     What is the major guide Descartes relied upon when deciding what hypotheses to formulate about the workings of the small parts of nature?

By imagining the simplest shapes bodies could have and the effects of collections of these shapes in motion (e.g., that balls slide past one another and so make things fluid; that pointed particles pierce and divide; that hook and eye shaped particles coalesce).  Observation of the workings of the machines we ourselves construct assists in doing this. (Princ. IV.203)

14.     Is there a role for experimentation in Cartesian science, and if so what is it?

There is no role for experimentation at the foundations of science, where the first principles governing the motion of matter and its nature are presented.  These principles are arrived at simply by clear and distinct perception on the part of the understanding. (AT VI: 63-64)  But when it comes to understanding the particular operations of particular bodies, we see that there many alternative mechanisms that might possibly produce the same result (just as there are many different ways to build a clock that still tells the same time).  The only way to determine which of these many different mechanisms is the actually operative one is to try to devise some sort of experiment capable of distinguishing between them, that is, a test situation that will turn out one way if one mechanism is the responsible one, and a different way if it is not.  It is here that experimentation and sensory experience end up having a role to play. (AT VI: 64-65)

 

16

Cartesian Science

(Discourse V, AT VI 40-45; Discourse VI, AT VI 63-65; Matthews, 99-108; Principles of Philosophy II.1-23 available in course packet or in The Continental Rationalists electronic database)

 

    1.     What is hardness, as far as our senses are concerned?  (This question and the following two are on the reading from Principles II.)

The sensation of strain we get in our muscles when we try to push or squeeze something and it does not yield. (Principles II 4.)

    2.     Why must the quantity of motion in the universe be preserved?

Because God, being a perfect being, is constant in the way he acts.  For Descartes this means that having once decided to create something, God will preserve that thing in existence.  Why constancy should have to be expressed in this particular way is unclear.  One might be constant by letting the quantity of motion continuously decay, or continuously increase, or continuously oscillate. (Matthews, 99-100, Principles II.36.)

    3.     Is it natural for bodies that have been set in motion to slow down and stop?  What is it that teaches us the answer to this, sense experience or understanding?

No.  We know this by understanding (specifically by a deduction from the constancy of God).  Sense experience teaches us that things naturally tend to rest, but this is only because all the bodies on the earth run into things that slow them down before long. (100-101, II.37)

    4.     Are there any random or chance occurrences in nature, according to Descartes?  (This question and the following two are on Discourse V.)

No.  Everything happens in accord with laws that are strictly followed. (AT VI 41)

    5.     In giving his account of the nature of matter in Discourse V, what features or properties did Descartes explicitly identify as ones he had no use for and did not need to suppose matter to have?

Aristotelian forms and sensible qualities really existing in things (42-43), and also weight (44).

    6.     How did Descartes respond to the objection that it is contrary to the creation story of the Bible to suppose, as he did, that all God needed to do to make the solar system, the Earth, the arrangement of water and minerals on the Earth, the weather, and the life on Earth, was institute certain laws and set an originally chaotic arrangement of matter in motion?

He has two answers.  The first is that he is merely describing a way God could have created the world and does not mean to deny that God actually created it in the more laborious way described in the Bible.  The second is that since sustaining the world from moment to moment actually requires that it be recreated at each successive moment (since the mere passage of the present into the past is continually destroying what now exists), it detracts nothing from God’s power or his governing role in creation to suppose that he could well have created the world in a different way. (45)

    7.     What do the nerves transmit to the brain? (This question and the following three are on the reading from Principles IV)

Nothing but motion.  Certainly not sensible qualities. (Matthews 105, IV.198)

    8.     Where does the feeling of titillation or pain, and the appearance of light and sounds originate from?

From within the mind.  In the external world and in the body, brain, and nerves there is nothing but parts in motion. (105, IV.198)

    9.     What makes it unlikely that the colours we sense are produced by colours actually existing on the surfaces of bodies?

If you are struck on the eye in a dark room, you see flashes of light even though there is nothing coloured around you.  This shows that colour is experienced as a consequence of motion in the object affecting the organ, not as a consequence of colour in the object affecting the organ. (105, IV.198)

10.     What is the major guide Descartes relied upon when deciding what hypotheses to formulate about the workings of the small parts of nature?

By imagining the simplest shapes bodies could have and the effects of collections of these shapes in motion (e.g., that balls slide past one another and so make things fluid; that pointed particles pierce and divide; that hook and eye shaped particles coalesce).  Observation of the workings of the machines we ourselves construct assists in doing this. (106-7, IV.203)

11.     Is there a role for experimentation in Cartesian science, and if so what is it?  (This question is on the selection from Discourse VI.)

There is no role for experimentation at the foundations of science, where the first principles governing the motion of matter and its nature are presented.  These principles are arrived at simply by clear and distinct perception on the part of the understanding. (AT VI: 63-64)  But when it comes to understanding the particular operations of particular bodies, we see that there many alternative mechanisms that might possibly produce the same result (just as there are many different ways to build a clock that still tells the same time).  The only way to determine which of these many different mechanisms is the actually operative one is to try to devise some sort of experiment capable of distinguishing between them, that is, a test situation that will turn out one way if one mechanism is the responsible one, and a different way if it is not.  It is here that experimentation and sensory experience end up having a role to play. (AT VI: 64-65)

 

17

Newton

(Matthews 137-39, 146-158)

 

    1.     Why is mechanics a more fundamental science than geometry?

Geometry does not tell us how to produce the figures, such as straight lines and circles, that it works with, since it is really just the study of how to measure these figures, but mechanics, being the science of motion and what can be produced by motion (geometrical figures are typically taken to be produced by the motion of points, for instance) does tell us how to produce figures. (M 137)

    2.     What is rational mechanics?

The study of motions and the forces required to produce them. (M 137-38)

    3.     What are the chief things that a rational mechanics of natural powers is concerned with?

Attractive and repulsive forces, such as those responsible for the motions associated with the phenomena of gravity, levity, elasticity, and hydraulic pressure. (M 138)

    4.     What is a natural philosopher supposed to uncover from an investigation of the phenomena of gravity, levity, elasticity, hydraulic pressure, and other such motions?

The forces responsible for those motions. (M138)

    5.     What does “reasoning from mechanical principles” consist of, according to Newton?

Starting from certain very general instances of motion and deriving the “forces,” i.e., the laws describing the manner in which these motions occur; then using these laws to account for all the particular instances of motion we see around us. (M138)

    6.     What did Newton speculate is the likely cause of all natural phenomena?

Attractive and repulsive forces operating between the particles of bodies in virtue of some causes hitherto unknown. (M 138)

    7.     What determines whether a quality is to be considered “universal” or not?

If it is present in all the bodies our senses ever reveal to us (“is universally present in experiments”) and does not come in differing degrees of intensity. (M146)

    8.     What are the universal qualities of all bodies whatsoever?

Extension, hardness, impenetrability, mobility, inertial mass, mutual gravitation (i.e, tending to move towards one another, not gravity understood as a property of heaviness since that is subject to remission), and possibly divisibility (though he later ruled this out). (M 147)

    9.     How do we know that bodies are extended?

By our senses. (M147)

10.     How do we know that even bodies so small we cannot see them are still extended and hard?

We know they are extended by induction from the bodies we do see, supposing that since these are extended those must be so as well.  We know they are hard because some of the bodies we feel are hard, and it is impossible for soft parts to make up a hard body, whereas a soft body can easily have hard parts arranged in some sort of lattice formation. (M147)

11.     List some of Newton’s chief objections to Cartesian vortex mechanics.

(i) It cannot give a consistent account of the speed of the parts of the vortices carrying the planets. (ii) It cannot account for the motion of comets.  (iii) It cannot account for the regularities in the design of the world, such as the fact that the planets and moons all orbit in the roughly same plane. (M148-49)

12.     How did Newton reply when asked to explain what causes gravitational attraction, and makes it always proportional to mass and inversely proportional to distance?

By saying that all we can know is that gravity works this way, because experience generally teaches us so, but that we cannot explain its cause and have no business formulating hypotheses on the matter. (M152)

13.     How did Newton reply when asked to explain what causes cohesion, electric and magnetic attraction and repulsion, the emission of light, and sensation?

By mentioning that they might be due to pressure exerted by a special kind of matter that permeates all things (a “subtle, elastic spirit”), but that we have no clear evidence on those matters yet. (M152)

14.     Did Newton think that motion is conserved?

No.  He rather maintained it is always decaying due to the “stiffness” of bodies in collision. (M153-54).

15.     What are the main active principles?

The cause of gravitation and the cause of fermentation (M154).  Also the cause of cohesion (M155).

16.     What properties did Newton speculate were originally put in particles by God?

Solidity, mass, hardness, impenetrability, motion, size, and shape. (M155)

17.     Why did Newton think it is unlikely that matter is infinitely divisible?

Because were the fundamental particles of which compound bodies like earth or water are composed to be divisible, it is likely that these compound bodies would not continue to have the same character over time, so that earth and water would be different at later times, not being built from the same kinds of parts.  But we have no evidence that any kinds of materials are changing their qualities. (M155)

18.     How did Newton justify the practice of explaining natural phenomena by appeal to qualities like gravitation, even though the causes of those qualities are occult?

By maintaining that he was not speaking of the causes of these qualities, but merely attempting to bring the observed phenomena under laws, justified by induction, and then use those laws to explain other phenomena. (M156)

 

17a

Newton

(Matthews 139-146)

 

    1.     Under what notions do common people conceive space and time?

Relative ones, which is to say that they conceive distances in space relative to landmark bodies presumed to be at rest, and intervals of time relative to certain cyclical events, as the rising and setting of the Sun or the changes of the seasons. (M139)

    2.     Does it make sense to say that an hour could take more or less time to pass?

It does.  An hour is 1/24 of the time it takes for the Earth to rotate on its axis.  Were the Earth to speed up in its rotation, an hour would take less time to pass, were it to slow down, it would take more time.  A reason to think this would not make sense is that were the Earth to speed up or slow down, it would have to speed up or slow down relative to some other measure of time, such as the length of time it takes for the Earth to orbit around the Sun, and then we would have to ask whether it was really the case that the Earth sped up in its daily rotation or whether it was instead its annual rotation that slowed down.  The only way to deal with such questions, it might be charged, is to simply pick some cyclical sequence of events, such as the time it takes for the Earth to rotate on its axis, and stipulate that it is the fundamental unit of measurement for all other processes.  In that case it would be impossible by definition for the Earth to speed up or slow down in its rotation, though other things could speed up or slow down relative to the Earth’s rotation.  This was not, however, Newton’s view.  In his view time itself exists apart from all the events that occur in time and passes with perfect uniformity so that it is the ultimate standard with reference to which all cyclical processes can be said to occur.  Any measure of time defined relative to some cyclical process could, in principle, speed up or slow down relative to the passage of absolute time. (M139)

    3.     List the properties of absolute space.

Homogeneity.  Immobility. (It is “always similar and immovable.”)  Possibly indivisibility as well, since that follows from the fact that one part cannot move relative to any of the other parts. (M140)  Earlier (M139), absolute space was also described as “true” and “mathematical,” in contrast to relative space, which is “apparent” and “common.”  Later (M141) immutability is added to the list.

    4.     How is relative space determined?

By the position of certain bodies. (M140)

    5.     How can absolute and relative space be the same in figure and magnitude, but different numerically?

Because a relative space can move around from one place to another in absolute space.  This happens when the bodies relative to which positions in the relative space are determined are themselves in motion in absolute space.  For example, a body can be supposed to be at rest relative to the Earth and so to occupy a place of the same figure and magnitude as itself (so a place that is numerically identical or coincident with it).  But if the Earth moves in absolute space, then the body would actually occupy a successive series of places in absolute space — places that are the same shape and size that is, but that are numerically different from one another because outside of one another. (M140)

    6.     How does absolute motion differ from relative motion?

Absolute motion is change of place in absolute space, relative motion change of place relative to certain bodies. (M140)

    7.     Why is it absurd that the parts of absolute space should move or change position relative to one another?

Because motion is change of place, and absolute motion change of place in absolute space.  A motion of a part of absolute space would have to be a change of place of a part of absolute space.  But absolute space just is the order of places relative to which all motion ultimately occurs.  If the places were to move, they would move out of themselves, as it were, to a different space, presupposing a yet more basic and immobile system of places that remains in station behind those that are moving, in which case the moving ones just are not absolute.  Whichever places are ultimately immobile, those are the absolute ones. (M141)

    8.     Why do we consider relative places and motions instead of absolute ones?

Because the absolute ones cannot be seen or otherwise distinguished by our senses, so we have no choice. (M142)

    9.     Why should we not rest content with relative places and motions in philosophical disquisitions?

Because there may be no body that is absolutely at rest, meaning that no space defined relative to body will provide a proper frame with reference to which to determine whether bodies are changing their state of motion. (M142)

10.     How can we distinguish absolute rest and motion from relative rest and motion?

By their properties, causes, and effects. (M142)

11.     Why can true and absolute motion not be determined by motion relative to surrounding bodies taken to be at rest?

Because those bodies may themselves be in motion.  If they are, then like a shell that contains a kernel, the inside bodies will partake of that motion even if they appear to be at rest relative to the surrounding bodies.  If, on the other hand, the internal bodies are in motion relative to the surrounding bodies then their true motion will be a sum of the actual motion of the surrounding bodies and their motion relative to the surrounding bodies.  In some cases (when the surrounding bodies are moving in the opposite direction with the same speed), the contained bodies may actually be at rest, even though they appear to be in motion relative to the surrounding bodies. (M142)

12.     What are the causes by which true motions are distinguished from relative motions?

The accelerative forces impressed on bodies. (M143)

13.     How can a true motion be preserved when the relative remains unaltered, and the relative preserved when the true alters?

True motion can be preserved when relative alters by causing the surrounding bodies to move.  In this case the contained body appears to move relative to the surroundings, even though it is really at rest and the surroundings in motion.  Relative motion can be preserved while true changes by causing both the contained body and the containing body to move together.  In this case there is no change of their relation to one another, even though they take on new motion in absolute space. (M143)

14.     What are the effects that distinguish relative from absolute motion?

The endeavour to recede from the axis of circular motion.  In a purely relative circular motion (where the surrounding bodies are the ones that rotate and the contained one is stationary) there is no evidence within the contained body of an endeavour to recede from the axis of rotation.  But in a real circular motion, where the body really is rotating in absolute space, its parts endeavour to recede from the axis of rotation, as can be evidenced by distortion of shape. (M143)

15.     What does the ascent of the water up the sides of the spinning bucket prove?

That the water is not just in motion relative to its surroundings but really in motion because its parts are endeavouring to recede from the axis of rotation. (M144)

16.     Why can true circular motion not be determined by rotation relative to any ambient bodies?

Because motion relative to ambient bodies is only relative motion, and we can have relative motion where there is no true motion as proven by the absence of an endeavour to recede from the axis of rotation.  When the bucket starts spinning and the water does not there is great relative motion (relative to the sides of the bucket, though not to the Earth or the fixed stars), but no true motion.  This is evidenced by the fact that the parts of the water do not attempt to recede from the axis of rotation even though we see from other circumstances that they are not welded together and are perfectly well capable of receding from the axis of rotation when the motion is real.  Given that there can be cases of relative motion where there is no true motion, we can never be sure that any ambient bodies we might pick on are not the ones that are actually rotating.  Pick the Earth, pick the fixed stars, or go out as far as you want.  The only thing this proves that it is the water that is really rotating and not the ambient bodies that you picked is the endeavour to recede from the axis of rotation. (M144)

17.     What is wrong with Descartes claim that the planets are at rest in their vortices even though the vortices are in motion around the Sun?

As long as the motion of the vortices is real motion, the Planets partake of it and will likewise attempt to recede from the axis of rotation along with the parts of the vortices, showing that they are really moved as well. (M144)

18.     Why is it a matter of great difficulty to tell true motions apart from apparent?

Because the parts of absolute space cannot be sensed or observed by us. (M145)

 

18

Locke, Essay Epistle and I.i.1-4,6-8; I.ii.1-9,12,14-16; I.iii.1-6,9,22,24-25; I.iv.1-5,8-9,24-25

(Innate Ideas)

the first five questions of this and the following chapter overlap

 

    1.     What was the main question that the Essay concerning human understanding was written to answer?

To determine the scope and limits of our powers of knowledge, or, as Locke put it, what objects our understandings are and are not fitted to deal with (Epistle: Nidditch, 7; Winkler, 2), and the origin, certainty, and extent of human knowledge, together with the grounds and degrees of belief, opinion, and assent (I.i.2).

    2.     What has so far served as the main impediment to the advancement of knowledge?

The imprecise use of words.  (Epistle: Nidditch, 10; Winkler, 2)

    3.     In what does the “Historical, plain Method” consist?

To examine the things we are originally conscious of, and the manner in which this original material is worked up by our minds into beliefs.  Also to use this information to determine how much of what we believe can be asserted as knowledge, and how much we are entitled to affirm on faith or as a matter of probability. (I.i.3)

    4.     What are the main consequences of a failure to inquire into the limits of what can be known by our understanding?

Dispute and scepticism, since we end up employing our faculties trying to answer questions they are not able to answer, end up indulging in wild speculations, disagree with one another because we can perceive no standard of truth, and end up doubting ourselves and our abilities and questioning everything. (I.i.7)

    5.     What does the term, “idea,” stand for?

Whatever it is that is before the understanding or that the mind can be said to be working with, when we think.  This is not a very helpful definition, but it is all that Locke said.  Most problematically, it leaves it unclear whether ideas are objects, like pictures, that are somehow looked at by the mind, or whether they are rather actions whereby the mind reaches an understanding. (I.i.8)  For a particularly clear expression of the former, see II.xi.17.

    6.     What is the argument from universal consent?

That the fact that there are certain things that are believed by all people in all times proves that these things are innately known. (I.ii.2)

    7.     What, in general, is wrong with the argument from universal consent?

The premise is false, since there are no principles that are known by all human beings whatsoever, and even if the premise were true, the conclusion would not follow because the universal knowledge may be based on some very common and evident experience. (I.ii.4 and 3)

    8.     What is wrong with supposing that there might be certain truths that we have always known and that were imprinted on our minds at birth, but that we are unconscious of?

If you do not have to be actually conscious of a proposition in order for it to be able to be considered to be in your mind, then there is no clear criterion for determining what is in your mind and what is not, and in principle any proposition could be said to be in your mind as long as it is true and is the sort of thing you are capable of knowing.  But if all that it means to say that you have innate knowledge of a proposition is that you are capable of knowing that proposition, then the claim is trivial and uninteresting and does not say anything that someone who believes that all knowledge is learned from experience could not just as well accept. (I.ii.5)

    9.     Did Locke deny that we have innate capacities?

No.  He thought that we have the innate capacity to know certain propositions, and that no one would deny this. (I.ii.5)

10.     What is wrong with supposing that there might be certain truths that we have always known and that were imprinted on our minds at birth, but that we need to employ reason to discover what they are?

Because reason is by definition the capacity to deduce something we do not know from other things that we have previously come to know.  So if something is known by reason, then by defintion it must have previously been unknown and so cannot have been innately known by us. (I.ii.9)

11.     What is wrong with supposing that there might be certain truths that we have always known and that were imprinted on our minds at birth, but that they only come into our consciousness when we attain the age of reason?

First, it is false, since there are no principles that are known by all human beings who have attained the age of reason.  Second, it is improbable, since there is no good reason why innate truths should suddenly pop into the mind just because our reasoning capacity has developed, especially since, as the answer to the previous question has shown, that capacity is unrelated to those truths. (I.ii.12,14)

12.     What is there about the fact that there are some truths that we come to know very early in life that actually goes to prove that these truths are not innately known?

The fact that these truths concern the ideas that are most commonly and readily obtained from experience.  This indicates that the truths are not known innately, but by gathering ideas from experience and comparing them with one another. (I..ii.15)

13.     Did Locke believe that there are absolute truths concerning what is right and wrong, or did he hold that moral rules are purely conventional?

He thought that there are absolute moral truths.  He just did not think that they are innately known.  The fact that different moral rules are accepted in different cultures is simply evidence for the fact that it is not obvious what the correct moral rules are. (I.iii.1)

14.     What reasons did Locke offer for rejecting the view that criminals still accept the truth of moral principles even though they do not act in accord with them?

First, that people’s practice is the best indication of what they really believe, and that even if it were not, the fact that their actions and even their explicit statements of what they value reject moral principles makes it impossible to say with any certainty that they do in fact still assent to those principles.  Second, that if something was really innately known as a practical principle then it ought to influence action.  This because a practical principle just is a principle concerning what to do.  A belief in a practical principle is therefore the same as a belief that one ought to act a certain way and hence as an inclination act in that way.  A principle that is believed without being acted upon is not really a practical principle, concerning what ought to be done, but a speculative one, concerning what is or is not the case.  So the possibility of assenting to a principle while not acting on it would imply that the principle is not in fact accepted as a practical principle. (I.iii.3)

15.     Did Locke deny that we have innate dispositions and tendencies?

No.  He supposed that we have innate dispositions to take pleasure or displeasure in things, and innate tendencies to desire or reject certain things.  He only denied innate knowledge and innate ideas. (I.iii.3)

16.     What are the main factors inducing people to take principles upon trust?

An inadequate opportunity to reflect caused by the demands of meeting the needs of life in those who are less affluent.  In the rest, one or more of ignorance, laziness, indoctrination, impatience, or having already accepted the principle that principles ought not to be questioned. (I.iii.24-25)

17.     What special reason does a consideration of the “parts” of principles give us for thinking that there could be no innate principles?

The parts of principles are ideas.  But most of the ideas that purportedly innate principles are made up of are so complicated and abstract that it is implausible to suppose they could be innately known.  But if the ideas are not innately in us, the principles they compose cannot be so either. (I.vi.1)

18.     What are the principal considerations leading Locke to deny that ideas are innate?

Observation of children, whom he claims give every indication of only having those ideas they have previously acquired from experience. (I.iv.2)

19.     What is Locke’s principal reason for denying that the idea of God is innate?

It is not had by all peoples. (I.iv.8)

 

19

Locke, Essay Epistle and I.i.1-4,6-8; II.i.1-8,20,23-25; ii, viii.1-6, iii-vi; vii.1-2,7-10

(Sensation)

the first five questions of this and the preceding chapter overlap

 

    1.     What was the main question that the Essay concerning human understanding was written to answer?

To determine the scope and limits of our powers of knowledge, or, as Locke put it, what objects our understandings are and are not fitted to deal with (Epistle: Nidditch, 7; Winkler, 2), and the origin, certainty, and extent of human knowledge, together with the grounds and degrees of belief, opinion, and assent (I.i.2).

    2.     What has so far served as the main impediment to the advancement of knowledge?

The imprecise use of words.  (Epistle: Nidditch, 10; Winkler, 2)

    3.     In what does the “Historical, plain Method” consist?

To examine the things we are originally conscious of, and the manner in which this original material is worked up by our minds into beliefs.  Also to use this information to determine how much of what we believe can be asserted as knowledge, and how much we are entitled to affirm on faith or as a matter of probability. (I.i.3)

    4.     What are the main consequences of a failure to inquire into the limits of what can be known by our understanding?

Dispute and scepticism, since we end up employing our faculties trying to answer questions they are not able to answer, end up indulging in wild speculations, disagree with one another because we can perceive no standard of truth, and end up doubting ourselves and our abilities and questioning everything. (I.i.7)

    5.     What does the term, “idea,” stand for?

Whatever it is that is before the understanding or that the mind can be said to be working with, when we think.  This is not a very helpful definition, but it is all that Locke said.  Most problematically, it leaves it unclear whether ideas are objects, like pictures, that are somehow looked at by the mind, or whether they are rather actions whereby the mind reaches an understanding. (I.i.8)  For a particularly clear expression of the former, see II.xi.17.

    6.     What are the two sources of ideas?

Perception of objects received through the senses and reflection on the operations on our own minds. (II.i.2-4)

    7.     What exactly is conveyed to our minds by our senses?

Something that manages to produce perceptions in the mind.  The relation between these perceptions and either their causes or objects existing in the world outside of us is so far unspecified. (II.i.3)

    8.     What are the “originals” from which our ideas “take their beginnings?”

External material objects and the operations of our own minds.  Note how Locke simply assumed the existence of an external world, without troubling about Cartesian doubt or thinking it needed to be addressed.  He seems also to have assumed some degree of resemblance between our ideas and objects.  This is implied by the reference to them as “originals” from which, presumably, ideas are made like copies. (II.i.4)

    9.     What evidence did Locke offer for supposing that all ideas originate from either sensation or reflection?

He hoped we would all agree that, upon performing a survey of the ideas in our minds, we do not find any that we did not either directly encounter in experience or construct from simpler ideas that we did encounter in experience (II.i.5)  He also claimed that a study of children shows no evidence that they were born with any ideas already in them (II.i.6).  Finally he observed that those brought up in very narrow environments, where there is little variety or change in the objects of experience, never manage to overcome the deficiencies of their circumstances to develop wider collections of ideas than just those they have managed to experience or build up by simply modifying ones they have experienced. (II.i.7)

10.     Do we only ever experience one simple idea at a time?

No.  Locke was explicit that the senses of sight and touch, in particular “often take in from the same object, at the same time, different ideas.”  He instanced motion and colour as well as softness and warmth.  He did hold, however, that the different simple ideas are perfectly distinct from one another, even though given simultaneously. (II.ii.1)

11.     What makes simple ideas simple?

They exhibit one uniform appearance, that is, there is no variety in their content. (II.ii.1)

12.     Is it possible for us to spontaneously create ideas on our own?

We can spontaneously create complex ideas by mixing together simple ideas we have previously been given in experience, but we cannot ourselves create new simple ideas.  We must instead learn of them through sensation and reflection. (II.ii.2)

13.     Do we have ideas of privations?

No.  Some of our ideas might be caused by privations (or better, objects that have slowed or stopped motions in our sense organs), but the ideas arising from these causes are as apparently positive as any other. (II.viii.1-2)

14.     What did Locke consider to be the likely causes of our ideas of white and black?

The kind and arrangement of particles on the surfaces of things. (II.viii.2)

15.     Did Locke think it is even likely that any of our ideas could be caused by privations?

No.  Not unless the state of rest or the state of moving in the opposite direction should be considered to be a privation rather than a positive state of being.  It is most likely, Locke thought, that all of our ideas of sensation are caused by motions communicated to our sense organs and that changes in those ideas are due to changes in the motions. (II.viii.1, 4, 6)  In that case, every idea whatsoever will be due to some real, positive cause, namely an alteration in the state of motion of the parts of the sense organs.

16.     What is solidity and how does it differ from hardness?

Solidity is one of the simple ideas received from the sense of touch.  It is a feeling of resistance that we get from bodies when we press against them.  For this reason, we think of this feeling as coming from a force of resistance to penetration present in the bodies.  Hardness, in contrast, has to do with the degree to which the parts of a body resist being moved relative to one another.  Things that are soft or fluid may nonetheless be very solid because they resist being compressed (e.g. water or hydraulic oil), so hardness is not the same as solidity. (II.iv.1 and 4)

17.     Why does the mind consider solidity to be a feature even of bodies that are too small to see?

Because of induction from what is universally the case with those bodies that it is able to see. (II.iv.1)

18.     What does it mean for a body to fill a space?

To fill a space is to exercise a repulsive force to resist the entry of any other body into that space.  A body that can be compressed, therefore, cannot be said to fill the space it occupies fully. (II.iv.2)

19.     How does the extension of body differ from that of space?

Space does not resist penetration, has inseparable parts, and is immovable.  An extended body is solid, has separable parts, and is movable. (II.iv.5)

 

20a

Locke, Essay II.viii.7-26

(Primary and Secondary Qualities)

 

    1.     Explain the difference between qualities and ideas.

Qualities inhere in bodies, ideas in minds — notwithstanding the apparently contrary indications of Locke’s occasionally sloppy usage (“Ideas … as they are modifications of matter in the bodies that cause such perceptions in us” — he should have said, “as they are taken to be modifications of matter”), (the Powers to produce those Ideas in us, … as they are Sensations or Perceptions in our Understandings” — he should have said “as they are distinguished by the Sensations or Perceptions they cause”). (II.viii.7-8)

    2.     What features must a quality have if it is to be considered primary?

It must be one that remains in a body regardless of what changes it may undergo, and one that our senses inform us is universally present in all our ideas of bodies. (II.viii.9)

    3.     How do the secondary qualities differ from the primary, if at all?

In virtue of the way particles with just the primary qualities are arranged, the collection of those particles can acquire a power to affect our senses in a particular way.  This power is the secondary quality, though it is something that results from the primary qualities of the aggregate of particles. (II.viii.10)

    4.     How do the tertiary qualities differ from the primary and the secondary, if at all?

Tertiary qualities are derivative from the primary qualities in the same way that secondary qualities are.  They are powers that the arrangement of the solid, shaped, movable, insensible parts of bodies gives to those bodies.  But whereas the secondary qualities are powers to bring about different sensations in us, the tertiary are powers to bring about alterations in other bodies. (II..viii.10)

    5.     How is it possible for one body to act on another?

Locke initially supposed that the answer is that this is only possible by communication of motion on contact (impulse). (II.viii.11)  However, in later editions of the Essay he acknowledged that Newton’s account of gravity might prove that there is another way this can happen.

    6.     Given that external objects are not only not united to our minds but even sometimes set at some distance from us, by what means do we come to perceive their original qualities?

Generally by some stream of insensibly small particles emanating from the surfaces of the bodies, hitting our sense organs, and bringing about motions in our nerves that are transmitted to the brain.  Note that on this account, what comes to be present in the brain as the cause of our ideas of the primary qualities of bodies does not resemble those qualities, except for being also extended, solid, and moving. (II.viii.12)

    7.     When Locke wrote in II.viii.15 that “the Ideas, produced in us by these Secondary Qualities, have no resemblance of them at all,” what were the ideas he was referring to, and what were the secondary qualities that he had in mind?

The ideas are our ideas of colours, smells, tastes, sounds, and other sensible qualities.  The secondary qualities are certain powers that bodies acquire, in virtue of the arrangement of their solid, shaped, and moving parts, to bring about these ideas in us. (II.viii.15)

    8.     What produces the idea of the motion and shape of a piece of manna in us?  What produces the ideas of sickness, acute pains, and gripings in those who have eaten a piece of manna?  What produces our ideas of the whiteness and sweetness of the manna?

In all cases, it is the solidity, shapes, motions and arrangements of the insensibly small parts of the manna, acting in concert. (II.viii.18)

    9.     What is the only effect that the pounding of an almond can produce in the almond?  What effect does the pounding of an almond produce in us when we perceive it?

All that pounding can do to the almond is break up it into parts and change the shape, size, and relative position of those parts.  Yet we perceive its colour and taste differently.  (The implication, of course, is that if all that is really happening is a change in the way the parts of the almond are shaped and arranged, then our perceptions of colour and taste must be consequences of the shape and arrangement of its parts, rather than of the presence of real qualities of colour and taste in the almond.) (II.viii.20)

10.     Under what conditions do we have an idea of the thing as it is in itself?

When we have ideas of the primary qualities of its parts.  This requires that the parts be large enough for us to perceive, which is the case almost exclusively with machines of our own manufacture.  Locke’s idea seems to have been that when you understand how the parts that go to make up a thing are shaped, arranged, and moving, you know everything there is to know about the thing as it is in itself.  You know precisely how its extension and solidity must be modified, and you know how it will change over time and interact with other things.  But when you don’t see down to the constitution of the constituent parts, you don’t know any of these things.  You can’t even be sure that the thing has exactly the size, shape, solidity, etc., it appears to have, since our sense perceptions of these qualities are sometimes distorted by factors such as distance and viewing angle.  So you don’t know the thing as it is in itself. (II.viii.23)

 

20b

Essay II ix.1-4,8-9; x.1-2; xi,1,4,6,8,9,15,17

(Perception)

 

    1.     Can we have ideas that go unnoticed by us?

No.  Locke’s position at the close of II.ix.4 is just that there can be unnoticed stimulation of the sense organs.  When that happens there simply is no idea produced.

    2.     What is the idea immediately imprinted on the mind when we see a black or golden globe?

A flat or plane circle, variously coloured and reflecting light to varying degrees. (II.ix.8)

    3.     What makes it “evident” that this is all there is to the immediate idea?

Locke took this to be evident from painting.  Probably this is an allusion to the fact that when a painter looks very carefully at a globe in order to depict it, he or she will notice that it does not in fact appear to be of one uniform colour.  Then, when the painter replicates the colouration on a flat surface, the result takes on a bit of an appearance of depth.  Locke was probably extrapolating from this to infer that all we really see is multi-coloured planes. (II.ix.8)

    4.     What was Molyneux’s question and what was his reason for answering this question in the negative?

Whether an adult who has been blind since birth, who knows how to identify geometrical shapes by touch, and who is suddenly made able to see would be able to tell, just by looking at a globe and a cube, which is which.  Molyneux thought the subject would not be able to make the identification because a newly sighted person would have no good reason to suppose that, just because an object feels a certain way, that therefore it must look a certain way.  So, even if the person could identify round and square visual shapes, the person would have no reason to suppose that what feels round would also have to look round.  It may also be that Molyneux thought that the feeling of a cube with angles prickling the palm would be nothing like the visual appearance of a cube, so that perhaps the blind person would not even see any reason to label the shapes on the visual field with the same geometrical terms used to name two-dimensional tangible shapes.  However, there is no reason to think that he believed that the blind person would not see colours to have extension and shape at all. (II.ix.8)

    5.     What moral did Locke draw from Molyneux’s negative answer to this question?

That it illustrates the extent to which ideas that we think we immediately perceive as a result of sensory stimulation may in fact have been created by unnoticed mental operations that transform more primitive and more immediately given ideas. (II.ix.8)

    6.     Explain Locke’s distinction between the role played by “perception of sensation” and “idea of judgment” in visual perception.  What is immediately perceived as a consequence of sensation and what is judged?

A “perception of sensation” is an idea that is immediately perceived as a consequence of sensory stimulation.  Not all ideas are perceived through sensation.  Some are created by mental operations (such as combination or abstraction) performed upon previously given ideas.  These ideas are said to arise from judgment.  In visual perception, the main perceptions of sensation are light and colours.  We have learned by experience that the qualities of light and colour are influenced in various ways by the distance, figure and motion of bodies (e.g., bodies seen at greater distances look to have fainter and more confused colouration).  As a result, we often take the immediately perceived light and colour to be signs that serve as the basis for a judgment about distance or other spatial properties that are not immediately perceived.  Often, the judgment occurs so rapidly and easily that we fail to notice the immediately perceived ideas that served as its premises, and mistakenly think we are immediately perceiving the distance or other spatial properties when in fact we are inferring it. (II.ix.9)

    7.     What is wrong with viewing memory as a storehouse for ideas we have had in the past?  What is memory if not a storehouse?

Ideas can only exist while they are being perceived.  When we cease to actively perceive them they cease to exist and therefore they cannot be supposed to remain in some storehouse.  Rather than be a storehouse for ideas not currently being perceived, memory is a capacity to recreate previously perceived ideas, together with the idea that they have been had before. (II.x.2)

    8.     How is it that particular ideas can be made to become general?

    9.     By considering them in isolation from the other ideas along with they happen to be perceived, particularly those ideas having to do with location in time and space. (II.xi.9)

 

21

Locke, Essay II. xii; xiii.1-5; xxii.1-5,9; xxiii.1-11,15-20

(Substance)

 

    1.     What is the difference between a complex idea and an idea of relation?

In a complex idea various simple ideas are combined together in such a way as to be considered to make up one thing.  In an idea of relation they retain their individuality and are merely compared with one another. (II.xii.1)

    2.     Identify two different ways in which simple ideas come to be united in complex ones.

Some are observed to be so united, others are united by an act of imagination even though they are not presented together in experience.  An example of the first would be the complex idea of an apple, that of the second the complex idea of a unicorn.

    3.     What is the difference between a substance and a mode?

A substance is a thing that can exist on its own.  A mode is something that cannot exist, even for an instant, apart from some other thing.  E.g., red is a mode because where ever there is red there must be some thing which is red.  Red cannot exist all on its own, independently of any thing.  That makes it a mode. (II.xii.6 and 4)

    4.     How do we arrive at our ideas of mixed modes?

In any of three ways: by arbitrarily combining various simple ideas in our own minds (invention), by finding simple ideas to be combined in certain ways in experience, or by means of words, when we hear a certain name for a mixed mode defined in terms of a certain combination of names for various simple ideas. (II.xxii.2-3, 9)

    5.     What gives unity to the various simple ideas in a mixed mode and makes them appear as one, single idea rather than an aggregate of distinct ideas?

The only things that are unified or one in a mixed mode are the one act of the mind in considering all the simple ideas together and the one name assigned to the mixed mode.  Locke considered the act of mind to be what first creates or gives rise to the unity, and the name to be the mark or sign of this unity. (II.xxii.4)

    6.     What conclusion do we tend to draw from the fact that different simple ideas are constantly observed to occur together in our experience?

That that these various simple ideas all belong to or better are all produced by one thing. (II.xxiii.1)

    7.     What is our notion of pure substance in general an idea of?

Some sort of support or holder for the different qualities that produce those different simple ideas that go commonly together in our experience.  That is, something in which qualities such as extension, solidity, and powers inhere.  However we have no clear idea of the nature of this substratum or of how it manages to hold or support qualities. (II.xxiii.2)

    8.     What is our notion of particular substances an idea of?

Some particular internal constitution or essence in this support or holder that determines the particular qualities that it supports or holds, and that also determines the way these qualities will change over time. (II.xxiii.3)

    9.     What leads us to distinguish material substances from spiritual substances?

Our inability to figure out how our ideas of reflection could belong to body or be produced by it, combined with a disposition to want to attribute these ideas to some sort of substance. (II.xxiii.5)

10.     What is our notion of matter an idea of, and how does it differ from our notion of spirit?

Our notion of matter is the idea of some support or holder for those qualities of bodies that affect our senses, that is, some substratum of the bundles of ideas we receive in sensation; our notion of spirit that of some substratum that performs the various operations exhibited in our ideas of reflection. (II.xxiii.5)

11.     What makes one person’s idea of a particular kind of substance more perfect than another’s?

It includes more of the ideas that the substance in fact brings about in us. (II.xxiii.7)

12.     What are the primary ideas we have peculiar to body? to spirit?

Cohesion and solidity or a power of communicating motion as a consequence of impact (“impulse”) in the former case, and a power of thought (notably of experiencing sensation as a consequence of impact on the sense organs) and a power of communicating motion by will in the other. (II.xxiii.17-18)

 

22

Locke, Essay II.xxi.1-5,7-11,13-15,22-25,29-33,40-48,51-53,56

(Power)

 

    1.     Is the idea of power a simple or a complex idea?

According to Locke it is simple.  Though Locke admitted that the idea of power, understood as the ability to either undergo or produce change, involves the thought of a relation to action or change, he did not consider this to be enough to make it an idea of a relation.  His excuse is that all ideas involve some relation.  In taking this position he was suggesting that the idea of power is not just the idea of a relation (say, of constant conjunction) between types of earlier and later states, but is an idea of some separate thing bringing about the change. (II.xxi.3)

    2.     What gives us our clearest idea of a power to begin motion?

Reflection on what we experience in ourselves when we will to move our bodies. (II.xxi.4)

    3.     What is will?

The power a person has to either bring about or change thought, or move a body part. (II.xxi.5)

    4.     What makes an action voluntary or involuntary?

Voluntary actions are those that follow upon a directive of the will, involuntary are those that are not effects of the will. (II.xxi.5)

    5.     Why can beings that have no will not be said to be free?  Why can beings who have will and who are doing what they will nonetheless be said to be necessitated?

Freedom is a power to either do or not do what is directed by the will, so it only exists relative to the will.  Beings that have a power to either perform an act or not but that do not have will (a power to prefer one course of action to the other) are not free.  Beings that have will but are either incapable of doing what they prefer or even incapable of doing the opposite of what they prefer are necessitated. (II.xxi.8)  The case of lacking freedom even though you do what you will to do is illustrated by II.xxi.10.

    6.     Explain the difference between the power of will and the power of liberty.

The power of will is the power to bring about an action merely by deciding and making the effort.  The power of freedom is the further power to prevent that action, supposing you had willed not to perform it.  (II.xxi.15)

    7.     What determines the mind to will what it does?

The most pressing among those things that make us uneasy which we think we are capable of removing.  (II.xxi.40)

    8.     What is required for a great good to determine the will?

Contemplation of that good.  Ordinarily we are distracted by the need to eliminate pains and other sources of uneasiness, which are more pressing and more readily resolved than great goods.  The only way a great good can come to influence the will is if we contemplate it and its advantages long enough to become uneasy as a consequence of our lack of the good.  (II.xxi.45-46)

    9.     What is the source of what is improperly called free will and of such liberty as we have?

A power we have to suspend desire.  (II.xxi.47)

10.     What causes us to be able to suspend action pending due examination of what is most conducive to our real happiness?

Whatever necessitates us to be strongly interested in pursuing our ultimate happiness.  (II.xxi.52)

11.     Why is it that we do not all always act in such a way as to obtain real happiness?

Sometimes extreme uneasinesses (arising from pain or strong passions) overwhelm us and do not allow us to suspend action (II.xxi.53).  Sometimes too hasty a choice of what is really conducive to happiness (II.xxi.56)

 

23

Locke, Essay II.xxvii.1-14

(Identity)

 

    1.     What is requisite if we are to be sure that one thing is different from another, e.g., that someone has a twin?

Seeing the one in a different place from the other at the same time. (II.xxvii.1)

    2.     What are the three kinds of substance?

God, finite minds or souls, and bodies. (II.xxvii.2)

    3.     Why is identity not a problem where God is concerned?

Because there is only one, omnipresent, eternal God.  So there can be no question whether or not a later God is the same as an earlier one. (II.xxvii.2)

    4.     Are there any exceptions to the rule that two different things cannot be in the same place at the same time?

Yes.  Any of the three different kinds of substances may coexist in a place.  So God, a soul, and a body could all be together in a place at the same time.  But no two things of the same kind could be in a place at the same time.  Two or more bodies could not be together in the same place at the same time, nor could two or more minds. (II.xxvii.2)

    5.     Under what condition would our ideas of identity and diversity have no foundation and be of no use?

If it were possible for two things of the same kind to be in the same place at the same time, then two or more things could be one thing, and then it would be impossible to apply the concepts of identity or diversity. (II.xxvii.2)

    6.     What determines the identity of particular instances of modes or relations and distinguishes different instances of the same mode (e.g., different right-angle isoceles triangles of the same colour and size) from one another?  What sorts of modes and relations can have no identity?

The same thing that determines the identity of substances: their having a common point of origin in space and time determines their identity and their being at different places at the same time determines their diversity. The modes or relations that cannot have this sort of identity are those that only exist in succession, like motion and thought, since in this case at each moment a different feature of the mode or relation comes into existence.  (II.xxvii.2)

    7.     If a mass of atoms has its parts rearranged, is it still the same mass?  If it loses or gains a part, is it still the same?

Rearrangement does not affect the identity of a mass, but loss or addition of even one part does. (II.xxvii.3)

    8.     What makes an oak tree different from a mere mass of matter?

Its parts are arranged in a particular way and engaged in performing those operations that are characteristic of that form of life. (II.xxviii.4)

    9.     What distinguishes one plant from another of the same species, e.g., one oak tree from another?

The fact that at some one moment, the organization of life-function performing parts characteristic of that species of plant exists in a different, organized collection of matter than does that of any other then existing member of the species. (II.xxvii.4)

10.     What determines that the organization of life-function performing parts that is present at any one instant in any one collection of matter is identical to one earlier or later organization of life-functioning parts characteristic of that species of plant rather than some other, e.g., that the bush in this pot in winter is identical to the one that was in the garden in summer?

That the organization of life-function performing parts that exists now preserves the same life as the earlier organization.  So, starting from the earlier moment and considering what particles entered the organization and what ones left it, as long as the alterations continued to preserve the same life, the plant is the same. (II.xxvii.4)

11.     How does the identity of animals and plants differ from that of machines?

In machines the organization of parts need not continually function to carry out the purpose for which the machine was designed, so the machine can stop running and start again and still be considered to be the same machine whether stopped, started, or stopped again.  But for the organization of parts in a plant or animal to cease to perform the life functions, the plant or animal would be considered to have died and to no longer be the same thing, but a corpse. (II.xxvii.5)

12.     What is wrong with supposing that what makes people the same from one moment to the next is that they look the same?

People look very different when they are newborn from what they look like when they are adult, and very different again when they are old and shrivelled up.  But we still think they are the same people. (II.xxvii.6)

13.     What is wrong with saying that what makes someone the same human being from one moment to the next is that they continue to possess the same soul?

For all we can tell, souls may be reincarnated into different bodies, perhaps even animal ones.  That would mean that we would have to consider someone who lived and died long ago to be the same human being as someone who is alive today, or even to consider some animal to be a human being.  And that is obviously not tenable. (II.xxvii.6)

14.     What was Locke trying to get at at II.xxvii.8 by claiming that a creature with a human body will always be considered a human being, even if it is so impaired as to be incapable of thought or sensation, whereas a cat or parrot who could speak and philosophize would still be considered a cat or parrot?

His point was that what makes you the same living creature from one moment to the next has nothing to do with your cognitive abilities but is simply a function of what sort of body you have.

15.     How do we distinguish our self from the selves of other thinking beings?

By means of consciousness, which Locke understood as a perception or awareness of the existence of all of our other thoughts or perceptions, including past ones.  I consider whatever thoughts or sensations I am conscious of to be what my self is, and whatever thoughts or sensations I am not conscious of to belong to other selves. (II.xxvii.9)

16.     What determines how far my self exists backwards in time, that is, what determines whether I will consider any past thought or action to be identical with a thought or action of myself?

My present self extends as far back in time as I can remember and those thoughts and actions that I can remember are what constitutes my past self. (II.xxvii.9)

17.     Does identity of self presuppose identity of thinking substance?

No.  Just as a succession of substances, preserving the same organization of parts, can constitute the same animal life, so a succession (or collection) of substances, retaining the same memories, can constitute the same self. (II.xxvii.10)

18.     What grounds do we have for affirming that the same person cannot be successively present in different thinking substances?

None other than the reflection that it would be incompatible with the goodness of God to allow this to happen, since then a soul might be punished at the last judgment for crimes it never committed.  But this is a matter of faith, and to get knowledge of the impossibility of this sort of transfer would require knowledge of the precise nature of the relation between a thinking substance and its thoughts and of the causes of memory and dreams, and this is knowledge that we do not have.  (II.xxvii.13)

19.     What grounds do we have for affirming that different persons could be successively present in the same thinking substance?

This would involve nothing more than stripping a thinking being of all of its thoughts and memories and having it start again with an entirely new set of experiences.  There is no evident impossibility in this.  (II.xxviii.14)

 

24a

Locke, Essay III.iii.1-4,6-13,15-18

(Abstract Ideas)

 

    1.     What does the meaning of words depend on?

At Essay III.iii.2 Locke remarked that the “signification and use” of words depends on their being associated with ideas.  So the meaning of a word, for Locke, is the idea it is taken to stand for.

    2.     What is the purpose of language?

It is used to communicate the ideas you are having to another person.  By speaking or writing words that name your ideas, you hope to arouse similar ideas in the mind of the person who understands those words. (III.iii.3)

    3.     How do words come to have a general meaning?  (Keep your answer to #1 in mind when dealing with this question.)

By being made to stand for general ideas.  (III.iii.6)

    4.     How do ideas come to be general?

By a process of abstraction performed upon particular ideas.  These ideas are given to us in perception as collections of many simple ideas occurring together and standing in certain relations of time and place to other collections of ideas perceived at the same time.  What we do is isolate (i.e., abstract) particular simple ideas from the collection and then combine just those ideas with one another to form a general idea.  What makes the idea general is that it can be used to refer to a number of other collections of ideas that also exhibit the particular simple ideas we have abstracted (though they would exhibit a number of other simple ideas as well). (III.iii.6)

    5.     Why is it particularly important that relations of time and place be removed when ideas are made general?

This one is not answered in the text and requires some ingenuity:  Because in the chapter on identity Locke identified location in space and time as the primary means by which one thing is individuated from another.

    6.     What do general words signify, according to Essay III.iii.12?  Why do they not signify a number of things?

Sorts.  That is, groups or classes to which many things belong.  That they signify groups or classes to which a number of things belong rather than directly signifying a number of things, is indicated by the fact that they are singular terms.  If they signified a number of things they would not have singular grammatical forms, but plural ones (e.g., insects rather than insect, or animals rather than animal).

    7.     What is the real essence of an individual substance?

That in a thing that makes it express the qualities and powers it does.  (On Locke's hypothesis, this is the fine constitution of the small corpuscles making up the thing.) (III.iii.15)

    8.     What is the nominal essence of a genus, sort, or kind of substance?

The abstract idea that is used to define the genus, sort or kind.  This idea is a list of simple ideas (and perhaps simple and complex modes) that a number of perceptions of things may have in common.  Whatever things give us perceptions that satisfy what is demanded on this list are considered to be of that genus, sort or kind for that reason.  It is in this sense that the abstract idea makes the genus, sort or kind what it is: it determines what things will be included and what will be excluded. (III.iii.15)

    9.     Are there any things whose real essences may be known by us?

Yes.  Simple ideas and modes, since in these cases the real essence, which makes the thing what it is, is just the nominal essence.  The real essence of a triangle, for instance, is just what we define a triangle as being, and that is a collection of simple ideas taken to be common to all triangles.  But in substances the real essence and the nominal are quite distinct. (III.iii.18)

 

24b

Locke, Essay III.vi.1-9,12,14-19,23,25-26,28

(Essence)

 

    1.     Locke observed that what appears like a star to us may look like a sun to the inhabitants of distant planets.  Why does this show that our classifications of things into sorts depends on what complex ideas we receive from them rather than on natures or essences in things that make them what they are?

Because it is one and the same object that appears as a sun to those close by and a star to those far off.  So its nature cannot be different and if it is nonetheless sorted into different groups by viewers at these different distances it is because of the different ideas they get of it at those distances. (III.vi.1)

    2.     How did Locke distinguish between real and nominal essence?

The nominal essence is the abstract idea we have formed of those complex ideas that each thing must give us in order to be considered to be of that sort.  The real essence is that in the thing (perhaps a “constitution of insensible parts”) that makes it give us all the characteristic ideas we get from it — those included in our abstract ideas, as well as any others that may be common to all the members of the group, even though we have not noticed it. (III.vi.2)

    3.     What is the nominal essence of human being?  the real essence?

The nominal essence is voluntary motion, sense, and reason in a body of a certain shape.  The real essence is the constitution human beings must have in order to give us the complex ideas listed in the nominal essence. (III.vi.3)

    4.     What must be the case before a particular individual can be considered to have an essence?

The individual must be considered as belonging to some group or other.  E.g., when Socrates is considered as a person, his essence is consciousness, when as a human animal, power of sense and motion attached to a body of a certain sort, when as a male, possession of certain sex organs, etc.  But considered just as an individual, Socrates has no nominal essence. (III.vi.4)

    5.     Can individual particulars, considered just in themselves and apart from reference to any group, have real essences? why or why not?

No.  The real essence is the foundation of those complex ideas that we get from all the members of a group.  So unless you specify what group you want to consider a particular as belonging to (e.g., as horse, as male, as thing with four legs that you sit on) you will not be able to specify what in its particular constitution is the foundation for those qualities. (III.vi.5)

    6.     Distinguish between real essence and real constitution.

The real constitution is the foundation for all the qualities that a particular thing exhibits and hence for all the ideas we get from it (III.vi.8).  The real essence is that part of the real constitution responsible just for the ideas that are listed in the nominal essence (as well as for whatever other properties might necessarily follow from this part of the real constitution). (III.vi.6)

    7.     What significance did Locke attach to the fact that we cannot explain why lead and iron are malleable, but antinomy and stones not, or why lead and antimony are fusible, wood and stones not?

It means we do not know the real essences that give these substances these properties. (III.vi.9)

    8.     What did Locke mean by saying that there are no “chasms” or “gaps” in the visible corporeal world?  (Note that he did not mean to deny that there is empty space or vacua.)

The chasms and gaps he is talking about are gaps between species of things.  His claim is that between any two kinds of things we always seem to be able to find individuals that are of an intermediate kind, in that they exhibit some of the features of both kinds. (III.vi.12)

    9.     What significance did Locke attach to the fact that different people understand the same kinds of things to have different nominal essences?

It indicates that these essences are created by the understanding, which in different people picks on certain similarities rather than others, depending on their “care, industry, or fancy” (III.vi.29, i.e., their degree of attention, their concerns, their past experience). (III.vi.26)

10.     If it is up to the understanding to construct nominal essences, then why are sheep-headed oxen and other fantastic arrangements of complex ideas not considered to be nominal essences?

Because the understanding is guided by what ideas we observe to commonly go together in perception, and we make no such observations. (III.vi.28)

 

25

Locke, Essay IV.i; ii.1-7,14; iii.1-14,17-18,21

(Knowledge)

 

    1.     What are the only objects the mind can immediately contemplate?

Its own ideas. (IV.i.1)

    2.     What is our knowledge of the coexistence of ideas particularly concerned with?

Substances.  We are concerned to determine what ideas do and do not belong together in our complex ideas of substances. (IV.i.6)

    3.     Are we capable of having knowledge of objects that exist outside of the mind?

According to the definition of knowledge in IV.i.2, all our knowledge is just of relations between our ideas.  IV.i.7 claims that we can also, at least in some cases, know of the actual existence of objects “agreeing” to certain of our ideas.  But note that in the strict sense, knowledge of real existence is merely knowledge that there is something corresponding to our ideas that exists outside of the mind.  To know that there is something corresponding to our ideas and to know what this thing is and how completely it resembles our ideas are two different things.  Just to know that there is something related to an idea without knowing what this thing is does not seriously overstep the definition given in IV.i.2.

    4.     What considerations led Locke to maintain that when you merely remember having demonstrated a conclusion, but do not review the proof, you still have knowledge of that conclusion rather than mere belief?

He came to think that the person who just remembers the result of a past demonstration is, in the very act of remembering it, performing a demonstration of that result, though a demonstration of a different kind from the original demonstration.  (In this demonstration the person first remembers that a certain conclusion was in the past perceived to follow from certain premises, then thinks that as long as things do not change or cannot change [because they are immutable], what was once perceived to be true of them must continue to be so, and from these two premises draws the previous conclusion again with all the force of a demonstration.) (IV.i.9)

    5.     What are the intervening ideas responsible for our remembered knowledge of the results of past demonstrations?

The thought of the “immutability of the same relations between the same immutable things,” i.e., the thought that if the things have not changed from what they were before, then their relations will have to be what they were perceived to be before.  Also the thought that certain relations were perceived before. (IV.i.9)

    6.     On what fundamental principle does our knowledge of all general propositions in mathematics depend?  Why must we rely on this principle?

The principle that, where immutable (unchangeable) things are concerned, what has once been perceived to be true of them will always be so.  We must rely on this principle if we are to think that what we have proven of a figure or number in one particular instance will remain true of that figure in all other instances.  And were we not able to generalize from one particular instance to others, all our mathematical knowledge would be of particular propositions, not of general ones. (IV.i.9)

    7.     Can memory ever be mistaken?

While this hardly seems correct, Locke seems to have thought that it is not really possible to misremember something, since he defined memory as “but the reviving of past knowledge” at IV.i.9.  However, in the last sentence of IV.i.9 he did recognize that it is possible for memory to fade and become unclear over time, so that it is no longer possible to remember what one once knew, or remember and hence know it as clearly.  This imperfection of memory does not degrade it from the status of knowledge, however.  (It is not tantamount to an admission that memory may ever be mistaken.)  It merely makes it a more “imperfect” form of knowledge than intuition, whatever that means.

    8.     Explain the difference between intuition and demonstration.

In intuition the relation between two ideas is directly and immediately perceived by the mind.  In demonstration it can only be perceived by means of an intermediate chain of ideas, each of which is intuited to be appropriately related to its predecessor and successor. (IV.ii.1 and 2)

    9.     Can demonstration ever be mistaken?

No.  Locke described demonstration at “certain” at IV.ii.4, and said that it “removes all doubt” in IV.ii.5, and that it is “very clear” at IV.ii.6.  These statements are incompatible with demonstration ever being in error.  But Locke does seem to have thought that while demonstration cannot be in error, people can be in error in supposing that they have demonstrated something when in fact they have not.  This can happen because of weakness of memory, which leads to a part of the demonstration being left out.  While memory cannot misinform us (see answer to question 7), Locke’s position seems to have been that we confuse demonstrations all the parts of which we cannot exactly remember with arguments that are not in fact complete demonstrations, and so end up accepting false conclusions.  However, it is not clear that this position is entirely coherent with the infallibility of memory insisted on in IV.i.9.

10.     What are we ultimately concerned with when we ask whether a particular idea in our minds corresponds to some object actually existing outside of us?

We are ultimately concerned with what will give us pleasure and pain.  An idea that we ourselves have cooked up in imagination cannot hurt us, nor can it benefit us, since it comes and goes as we see fit (except, of course, in certain dreams).  But if the idea comes from an object, and that object has powers in it to bring about further ideas of pleasure and pain in us, then we think that, depending on how we behave, we will get ideas of pleasure and pain (or fail to get them) from that object independently of our wills.  Thus it is a concern with the connection between our ideas of pleasure and pain and our ideas of objects that motivates a concern with determining what ideas actually are of objects existing outside of us. (IV.ii.14)

11.     What effects can we intuit or demonstrate motion to be able to produce?  What effects do we perceive it to produce?

Motion can be conceived to produce nothing other than motion, but we perceive that it is somehow able to produce ideas of colours, pleasure and pain, and other such things in us. (IV.iii.6)

12.     If we were able to determine the primary qualities of the insensibly small parts of which bodies are composed, would we then be able to deduce what ideas those bodies are and are not able to bring about in us?  Why or why not?

We could possibly deduce what type (i) ideas we would get of the primary qualities of bodies, but since there is no apparent connection between the primary qualities of bodies and our type (ii) ideas of sensible qualities (which Locke here referred to as “secondary qualities,” contrary to his official definition), even knowing the real constitution of bodies would not allow us to deduce what type (ii) ideas those bodies might or might not bring about in us. (IV.iii.13)

13.     Upon what, ultimately, must we rely for our knowledge of what qualities and powers may coexist in any given substance?

Sensory experience.  Only by seeing the substance actually exhibit those qualities or powers can we tell.  We cannot learn about just a part of its nature and then hope to deduce the remainder, because most of the qualities and powers in bodies have no necessary connection with any others, so that from the fact that a body has certain ones, it does not follow that it has any others. (IV.iii.14)

 

26

Locke, Essay IV.iv.1-12; ix.2-3; x.1-7; xi

(Knowledge of Real Existence)

 

    1.     What assures us that our perceptions of simple ideas are not made up by us but correspond to powers in bodies?

The fact that we are only able to get these ideas when our sense organs are suitably affected.  Were the ideas innate or such that we could create them from a mere act of imagination, then we could doubt whether they correspond to powers in bodies.  But since they only first originate in us after our senses have been affected in a particular way, and no one can get these ideas without having that happen (even talking to others who have had them is not enough to make the conception of them arise in the mind, just as the blind can have no concept of colours), we can be sure that there must be some power in the objects that affect our senses to produce them. (Essay IV.iv.4)

    2.     Why can mathematical principles be regarded as “true and certain” even though they only describe ideas we have ourselves created in imagination?

Because if any actually existing objects were to exactly conform to what we think as defining the shapes and numbers we consider in mathematics, whatever we demonstrate of those shapes and numbers would also have to be true of these actually existing objects. (IV.iv.6)

    3.     What is the basis for our knowledge of general truths?

Demonstrations proceeding on the basis just of what is contained in the ideas involved in those propositions.  Otherwise put, general principles are known by analysis of their component terms or by intuiting relations between their component terms.  Since these principles are true whether or not any of the things they talk about actually exists, their truth has nothing to do with the real existence of things, but only with relations of the ideas they contain. (IV.iv.8)

    4.     Are there any constraints on the power of the imagination in constructing ideas of complex modes?

We cannot put ideas together in such a way as to create a contradiction. (IV.iv.12)

    5.     What conditions must be satisfied in order for our ideas of substances to be considered real rather than imaginary?  What conditions must be satisfied for them to be considered at least possibly real rather than fantastic creations that could never even possibly exist?

To be considered real the simple ideas that are combined in the substance must be actually experienced to go together in perception.  To be considered at least possibly real, that collection of simple ideas must have been experienced to go together at some point in the past.  (Since we do not know the real constitutions responsible for giving things the powers they have to bring about the ideas they do, we cannot automatically assume that just any two simple ideas may be combined together in a substance, for the real constitutions needed to produce those simple ideas may be incompatible and incapable of coexisting.  The only way we can be sure the combination of simple ideas is even possible, therefore, is if we have actually experienced some substance exhibiting them.  The bare fact that they do not contradict one another is no indication.) (IV.iv.12)

    6.     Is it possible to prove our own existence, i.e., give a demonstration of the fact?

No.  You know of your own existence by intuiting that your thoughts must belong to some substance.  While demonstrations are a chain of intuitions, in strictness something that is intuitively evident on its own is not demonstrated.  You need more than one intuition to make a chain. (IV.ix.2 and 3)

    7.     Did Locke accept the causal principle (that every effect must have some cause)?  If not, why not, and if so, how did he think we come to know it?

Yes.  He claimed we know it by "intuition," which means we must just see its truth immediately by inspection of our ideas. (IV.x.3)

    8.     What significance does the power to produce and remove ideas have for Locke’s arguments to demonstrate the existence of an external world?

The fact that we cannot produce new ideas on our own (as evidenced by the fact that blind people can form no ideas of colours or those who have never tasted pineapple realize what it tastes like) is an indication that there must be different things in the environment around us that act on our sense organs and so give them the stimulus to originally produce ideas.  The fact that we can call up some ideas out of memory and send them away again is an indication that those ideas are imagined, whereas the contrary fact that there are some ideas that we cannot call up or dismiss at will is an indication that there must be something else that is imposing those ideas on us. (IV.xi.4 and 5)

    9.     What significance do feelings of pleasure and pain have for Locke’s arguments to demonstrate the existence of an external world?

Locke believed that the imagination could not produce feelings of pleasure and pain, so that when these feelings accompany an idea, it is a sure sign that the idea is being perceived and not imagined.  He considered reality itself to consist in whatever can produce pleasure or pain or serves as a reliable sign for what can produce pleasure or pain.  On this account, if dreams and fantasies could produce pleasure and pain then they would be as good as real for us and would have to be treated as such since they would determine our happiness and change our state of well being.  Otherwise put, a dream or fantasy is only a dream or fantasy if it does not produce feelings of pleasure or pain.  The conclusion, once again, is that where these feelings arise, we can be sure we are dealing with reality. (IV.xi.6-8)

10.     Can I know that objects continue to exist when I am not perceiving them?

No (IV.xi.9).  We can know that they existed (in the past) if we remember having perceived them (IV.xi.11), but our conviction that they exist now can never be more than probable.  We can only be certain that they continue to exist when we are actually perceiving them.  — But there is no reason why we should not rest content with mere probability in these matters. (IV.xi.10)

11.     Can I know that other human bodies think and perform acts of will?

No.  For Locke this is something that falls short even of probability and has to be accepted merely on faith. (IV.xi.12)

 

27

Locke, Essay IV.xiv-xv; xvi.1,3-14

(Probability)

 

    1.     Why did God not make us capable of knowing more things?

To keep us from becoming too confident and make us more careful and hesitant in our assertions (IV.xiv.2)

    2.     Why is judgment exercised?

Because knowledge cannot be obtained yet the circumstances of life compel us to make a decision.  But also because, even though a demonstration is available and within our grasp, we are too impatient, lazy, or stupid to work it out. (IV.xiv.3)

    3.     Can a proposition be both certain and probable at one and the same time?

Yes, if it is entertained by two different people.  Certainty and probability do not concern the proposition but the person who entertains it.  If the person intuits or is able to demonstrate the truth of the proposition, then it is certain for that person.  But another person may not be able to do this, or may accept the proposition on the basis of evidence that is less than certain, for example, the say-so of someone else. (IV.xv.1)

    4.     How can Locke say, without contradicting himself, that the testimony of others is one of the two grounds of probability (IV.xv.4), and that the opinions of others are no true grounds of probability (IV.xv.6)?

When he talks about the testimony of others as being a ground of probability, he means their testimony to things that they know because they have demonstrated, or experienced them.  Opinions are not things they know but things they believe to be the case on the basis of a judgment based on evidence. In that case, they should tell us what that evidence is so we can be informed to make our own judgment and not just tell us what their beliefs are and expect us to swallow them.  We are to accept testimony only when it is testimony to what someone has experienced or demonstrated, not just testimony to what someone believes.

    5.     Under which, if any, of the following circumstances could a person be said to have violated Locke’s ethics of belief?

                            a.     a person reaches a decision without having fully examined the issue

                            b.     a person sticks to a decision made earlier merely because they remember having decided that way earlier, and without bothering to remember the evidence for that decision

                            c.     a person sticks to a decision made earlier without bothering to review new evidence that has since come in

                           d.     a person sticks to a decision made earlier even after having been confronted with evidence that undermines that decision

In none of them.  Locke wrote that the demands of life often compel people to make decisions upon matters when they have not been able to review all of the pertinent evidence, and that few actually have the leisure, resources, and patience to be able to collect all of the relevant information. (IV.xvi.3)  No one can therefore be blamed for reaching a decision upon an incomplete survey of the evidence.  However, people can be blamed for reaching a decision without sifting matters to the best of their ability, at the time that they were obliged to reach their initial decision. (IV.xvi.3)  Locke also wrote that retaining all the evidence for a decision once reached in one’s memory is too hard, and that no one should be expected to have to do that as long as they can clearly remember that they did reach that decision in the past upon surveying the evidence to the best of their ability at the time. (IV.xvi.1)  Finally, he wrote that reviewing all the evidence that is continually coming in would be too burdensome for people to be obliged to do it, given their minimal amount of leisure time, resources, and patience and the pressures of everyday life (IV.xvi.3), and that since reliability and steadfastness are also virtues, people cannot be expected to abandon their opinions even in the face of contrary evidence, as long as that evidence does not amount to a demonstration.  For, anything short of a demonstration could be wrong, and any who abandon one opinion for another merely as the evidence swings back and fourth end up being too inconstant in their opinions. (IV.xvi.4)

    6.     Is intolerance ever justified?

Hardly ever.  If you have good reason to suppose that a person could easily have performed a more adequate survey of the evidence before reaching their initial decision, or if you are actually in possession of a demonstration that is fairly direct and easy to grasp, then you might be able to criticize the person for their beliefs, but simply having stronger evidence does not entitle you to even expect the other person to consider your evidence. (IV.xvi.4)

    7.     Explain the difference between assurance and confidence.

To have assurance you must be told of the occurrence of some matter of fact (i.e., something concerning the qualities, powers, causes, or effects of some substance or group of substances) you did not yourself experience (if you did experience it you would have sensation and not belief).  Moreover, all the witnesses must agree that the matter of fact occurred.  Finally, the matter of fact must be of a type that both you and everyone else have always observed to be true in the past; that is, it must be a consequence of a universal law of nature, such as that stones fall or fire burns.  For confidence all of these same conditions must be met except for the last one.  If the matter of fact is one that is sometimes true and sometimes false, but could as well be true as false or is most often true, then you can have confidence, but not assurance.  Assurance is thus a higher degree of belief. (IV.xvi.6-7)

    8.     What are the main causes of diminution in the probability of testimony to a matter of fact?

Conflict of the testimony with common experience, with the regular course of nature, or with other testimony. (IV.xvi.9)

    9.     What are the two “foundations of credibility?”

What has been commonly observed in similar cases in the past, and the quality of the testimony in favour of what happened in this particular case. (IV.xvi.9)

10.     What is a “traditional” testament?

One received at second or third or a more remote hand. (IV.xvi.10)

11.     What are some of the main reasons leading people to misrepresent someone else’s testimony?

Passion, vested interest, oversight, and misinterpretation. (IV.xvi.11)

12.     Is it possible to have any sort of assurance or confidence about the existence of things that fall outside of anyone’s capacity to observe, such as the insensibly small, the insensibly remote, or the hidden mechanisms in causes responsible for giving them the power to bring about their effects?  If so, how so, if not, why not?

We can have some probable conjecture about these matters based on the assumption that unobservable things will be relevantly analogous to observable things.  The stronger the analogy, the greater the probability of our belief can be. (IV.xvi.12)

13.     Why can we have assurance in the occurrence of well-attested miracles, despite the fact that they are contrary to common experience and the regular course of nature?

Because if beings exist that are powerful enough to alter the course of nature, we should expect that they would do so in those circumstances where they have ends or goals that might be served by such an intervention. (IV. xvi.13)

14.     Besides being contrary to the ordinary course of observation, what further feature must an event have before it can be considered a miracle?

It would have to be supposed to serve some purpose that a supernatural agent could reasonably be supposed to have. (IV.xvi.13)

15.     What is faith?

Belief in the testimony of a being who knows all and would not lie. (IV.xvi.14)

16.     What conditions must be satisfied before we can have faith in a revelation?

We must know that the revelation in fact came from God, and we must be assured that we have interpreted it correctly. (IV.xvi.14)

 

28

Locke, Essay IV.xviii.1-10; xix

(Reason, Faith, and Enthusiasm)

 

    1.     Would Locke consider any merely probable judgment to be known by reason?  Would he consider propositions known by intuition or sensation to be known by reason?

At IV.xviii.2 he defined reason as the discovery of the certainty or probability of propositions by means of deductions.  However, judgments based on revelation are also probable, and Locke distinguished faith from reason in this passage as well.  Thus, for Locke, reason would include demonstration and all forms of probable judgment other than faith.  But it would exclude intuition and sensation (since they do not involve “deductions” but rather are immediate forms of knowing) as well as faith.  However, at IV.xviii.3 he used the term “reason” more broadly to include whatever is taught to us by our “natural” faculties and so here included intuition and sensation as part of “reason” and excluded only faith.

    2.     Explain Locke’s distinction between original and traditional revelation.

When a person is themselves the subject of a religious experience, they have an original revelation.  When a person believes a certain revealed truth, not because they have themselves experienced it to be revealed, but because they have accepted someone else's report (perhaps at second or third or more remote hand), then they get their belief from a tradition rather than personal (original) experience. (IV.xviii.3)

    3.     What is required for us to put faith in a traditional revelation?

We have to know that the tradition that hands this revelation down to us is reliable (e.g. that books really were written by those who received the revelation, that copies are accurate, etc.). (IV.xviii.4)

    4.     What is required for us to put faith in an original revelation?

We have to be sure that what has been revealed to us did in fact come from God and was not induced by something else (say delirium caused by too much fasting, fever, trance, mental disease, or drugs).  We also have to be sure that we have understood the message correctly. (IV.xviii.5)

    5.     If revelation tells us something that reason denies, which must we accept according to Locke and why?

Reason.  Locke's position is that we are in fact constitutionally incapable of doing otherwise (except in the case of those suffering from the mental disease of enthusiasm, which he discusses in the next chapter).  This is because we cannot help but put our belief in that relation of ideas that we perceive most clearly.  And given the answers already supplied to questions 4 and 3, there must always be some residual doubt attached to a traditional revelation — either about the authenticity of its source or the reliability of its tradition.  Nor can this doubt be removed by a further, original revelation that the traditional revelation is true.  For even in that case we would still need to employ reason to decide if the message really came from God and was correctly understood, which means we have to put trust in reason before faith.  Thus, the proposition that a particular revelation is good ground for faith can never be as trustworthy as the clear perception of a relation between ideas. (IV.xviii.4-6)

    6.     If revelation tells us something that reason tells us nothing about, which must we accept according to Locke and why?

Faith.  But we must use reason to make sure that the revelation came from God. (IV.xviii.7)

    7.     If revelation comes into conflict with a proposition that our reason judges to be probably true, which must we accept according to Locke?  In virtue of what do we decide which we must accept?

Faith, supposing that reason demonstrates that the revelation did come from God and the message has been correctly understood.  Our decision is grounded on the fact that as long as reason is not able to demonstrate that the opposite of what faith tells us as impossible, we ought to accept the testimony of a witness who knows all and would not lie.  Insofar as we have reason to think that God is the witness, we are dealing with such testimony. (IV.xviii.8-9)

    8.     Could someone who comes to form a belief after an incomplete survey of all the evidence still be called a lover of the truth?

Yes.  They could only be said not to love the truth if they assented to the proposition with more or less conviction than was warranted by such a survey of the evidence as they had managed to perform.  For Locke, to love the truth means merely to not accept a proposition with any more or less certainty than the evidence that you have examined warrants.  However, that a love of the truth should compel a survey of all the available evidence is not something he suggests, and is something IV.xvi.1-4 condemns as impractible. (IV.xix.1)

    9.     What is the principal cause of intolerance?

Lack of love and respect for the truth.  Someone who does not love the truth is apt to affirm a proposition with more conviction than the evidence warrants.  And someone who is unjustifiably certain of a proposition is apt to expect others to accept it as well and be indignant with them if they fail to do so (which is likely if the proposition is not in fact certain).  Moreover, since this person will have ignored the voice of their own reason, and so imposed a belief upon themselves in the absence of true evidence, it is only to be expected that they will exercise the same violence on others. (IV.xix.2)

10.     What is enthusiasm?

Putting faith in a revelation that has not been shown by reason to have come from God. (IV.xix.3)

11.     Why does enthusiasm destroy the authority of revelation as well as reason?

Enthusiasm places revelation above reason.  But if we don’t place reason above revelation, we cannot use reason to distinguish what is truly a revelation from what only pretends to be one and take away the source from which revelation gains its support. (IV.xix.4)

12.     What is immediate revelation and what considerations lead people to suppose they have it?

Immediate revelation is like original revelation in being a direct communication of an individual with God.  But unlike original revelation it is supposed to be evidently a message from God and is not taken to stand in need of authentication by reason.  Thus, it is a form of enthusiasm.  If enthusiasm is putting faith in a revelation that has not been shown to have come from God, immediate revelation is putting faith in a revelation you imagine to have yourself received from God, even though you have no rational warrant for doing so.  People believe they have it because it is not impossible that God might in fact have given it to them, because if they can suppose that something has been revealed by God they can avoid the hard work of finding it out by other means, or can maintain it even though it is strictly unprovable by any other means, and because it flatters their pride to imagine God has chosen them for a special communication. (IV.xix.5)

13.     What are the chief causes of enthusiasm, according to Locke?

Laziness, ignorance, and vanity.  The enthusiast is someone who is too lazy, too impatient, or too afraid to embark on the hard work of doing research guided by reason.  The enthusiast prefers quick and easy answers instead and is willing to sacrifice love of the truth to get them.  And the enthusiast is flattered by the fancy of having been specially chosen by God for communication. (IV.xix.8)

14.     What is the main question that must be asked about an immediate revelation?

Did it come from God, from some other spirit, or from one’s own fancy? (IV.xix.10)

15.     Why can immediate revelation not truly be “seeing?”

Because were it “seeing” I would know it to be so simply by inspecting the ideas involved and seeing their relation to one another (this is what happens in intuition) or by having an experience where the ideas are so connected.  In the first case anyone else with those same ideas should intuit the same thing.  In the second case, anyone else in the same circumstances should sense the same thing.  But in fact, those claiming to have immediate revelations are not claiming to simply see but to have something revealed to them by God, so that the case is not actually one of intuiting or sensing but rather one of accepting something on God’s purported say-so, even though the visionaries claim to be “seeing.” (IV.xix.10)

16.     How can we know that a revelation has in fact come from God?

By means of some outward sign such as a miracle. (IV.xix.15)  In cases where that is lacking, the revelation must be conformable to already authenticated revelations. (IV.xix.16)

 

29

Bayle

Dictionnaire, “Pyrrho B”

(references are to the text in ECCO; “r” is right hand column, “l” left-hand column)

 

    1.     How does the position on ethics that Bayle attributed to Pyrrho differ from Locke’s position on ethics?

Locke believed that ethics could be known by demonstration whereas Pyrrho held that they are merely conventional.  In the main text of the Pyrrho article, Bayle took Pyrrho’s position to naturally follow from his view that the absolute internal constitution of things cannot be known, so that we might as well simply accept whatever laws and customs happen to be in effect in a given society.  While Locke also believed that the real constitution of substances cannot be known, he took our knowledge of ethics to be based on knowledge of complex modes, which can be known. (p. 2622 of the main article)

    2.     Why is scepticism not dangerous to science or to the state?

Because the scientists are all sceptics already (since none of them believe that we can know what is ultimately responsible for the phenomena of nature — the Cartesians believe we can only make hypotheses about it and the Newtonians that we can only describe its laws, and Locke insisted we cannot know the real constitution of things), and the sceptics always said that since we can’t know for sure what is right or wrong or how we ought to behave, we might as well just follow whatever laws and customs happen to be in effect in our societies. (p.2619-r of Note B)

    3.     Why is it dangerous to religion?

Because if you have any doubts in religious matters you will lose your faith in the religion and no longer be willing to observe its rituals or other practices. (2619-r)

    4.     Why is this danger only slight?

Because the sceptical arguments are not very effective means of persuading most people. (2619-r)

    5.     What shields us against Pyrrhonian arguments?

The Grace of God which compels those who receive it to believe, the force of education, ignorance of those arguments, and our natural instincts, notably a natural instinct to want to have answers to things and to be dissatisfied with uncertainty. (2619-r)

    6.     Why would Arcesilaus be more formidable today than in his own time?

Because Christian theology and the new natural philosophy would give him unanswerable arguments against all those who suppose that it is possible for us to comprehend things. (2620-l)

    7.     What were the ancient sceptics right about, according to the “new philosophy?”

That sensible qualities are only appearances. (2620-l)

    8.     What do the new philosophers attempt to exempt extension and motion from?  Why are they unable to actually do this?

From the claim that they, like the other sensible qualities, are only appearances in us and not true qualities of bodies.  They were not actually able to do this because if bodies can appear to us to be coloured, hot, cold, and odiferous without really being so, then they can just as well appear to us to be extended and moving without really being so. (2620-l)

    9.     Why do I have no good proof for the existence of bodies?

Bayle’s argument rests on the premise that bodies cannot be the cause our sensations, so we cannot infer that bodies exist from the fact that our sensations exist.  Bayle did not say why bodies could not be the causes of our sensations.  A popular argument at the time was that because minds are such radically different things from bodies, it is inconceivable how bodies could act on minds to cause them to have sensations.  Another argument would appeal to the possibility of experiencing objects in dreams.  (2620-1)

10.     Why would it prove too much to claim that God would be a deceiver for giving me ideas of extended things if there are no extended things in existence?

Because the same argument would also prove that these extended things must have the qualities our senses reveal them to have, and all the "new philosophers" deny this. (2620-l)

11.     In what way is a peasant like a Cartesian?

Their beliefs are equally instinctive and equally deniable, so if God does not deceive peasants by giving them an instinctive belief that fire is red and hot even though it is not he would not deceive Cartesians by giving them an instinctive belief that fire is extended and moving even though it is not; on the other hand, if God would be a deceiver for giving the Cartesians a natural impulse to think fire is extended and moving, he would be just as much of a deceiver for giving peasants a natural impulse to think fire is red and hot. (2620-l)

12.     What entitles us to think that the principle of the transitivity of identity (that is, that if a=b and b=c, then a=c) is wrong?

The mystery of the Trinity, which teaches us that though the Father is God and Christ is God, Christ is not the Father.  Since the Christian revelation proves this principle to be true, and the principle contradicts the principle of the transitivity of identity, we must conclude that the transitivity of identity is false. (2620-l-r)

13.     Why should I think that even though I am here in Canada, I might also at this moment exist in Constantinople?

Because the mystery of the Eucharist assures us that one and the same body can be in two different places at the same time. (2620-r)

14.     How is it that the mystery of the Eucharist invalidates all the rules of arithmetic?

Because it makes it possible that things we count up as two or more may in fact be just one thing. (2620-r)

15.     What assures me of the fact that I existed yesterday?

Nothing more than faith in scripture, which tells us that our souls will be judged for their deeds during life at the last judgment, a claim that implies we must last for more than a moment.  But there is nothing in memory or in the nature of things that could provide this certainty.  The doctrine of constant creation entails that a new soul could possibly be created for each person at each successive moment of time, and that this soul could have all the memories of the previous soul implanted in it.  Thus, there need be nothing discernible to memory were I newly created, and there would be no physical impossibility in such an occurrence. (2621-r)

 

29a

Bayle

Dictionnaire, “Zeno F and G”

 

    1.     Why could there be no moment at which a moving arrow moves?

Because if it moves at a single moment it would have to be in two places at once, which is impossible.  It follows that in a single moment a body can only occupy a space equal to itself, which means that over any single moment any body must be at rest and not in motion, since it is not going anywhere in that moment.  (608-l-r)

    2.     Why is it impossible for a moving object to go from one extremity to the other?  What important distinction between matter and time is involved in this answer?  What absurd consequence would follow if an object could go from one extremity to the other?

Because there are infinitely many parts between the extremities and it is not possible for a moving body to be at more than one of them at a time.  Given infinitely many points to be touched and at least one moment occupied in touching each of them, it follows that the interval between extremities could never be crossed.  This answer supposes that, unlike time, the space or “matter” between extremities is infinitely divisible — indeed, infinitely divided or marked off by a moving object, which must pass over or touch on each of its infinitely many parts in succession.  Given this is the case the only way a body could make it from one extremity to the other is by touching more than one part of space at once.  But that is absurd because it implies that the body would be in more than one place at once.  (609-1-r)

    3.     Why could an hour neither begin nor end if time were composed of an infinite number of parts?

Were time infinitely divisible, there would have to always be a further moment between any two given moments.  Given that no two moments can coexist, each must pass before the next can come to be.  But if there are always further moments between any two given moments, then there will always be some further intervening moment that first needs to pass before getting from the first of two given moments to the second, which is tantamount to saying that we will never get to the second moment because there will always be some intervening moment that needs to pass first before we get there.  Consequently, time could not pass.  Since it does pass, it could not be infinitely divisible. (609-r)

    4.     Identify three things that cannot be reconciled with the idea that a moving body might simultaneously move with two different speeds relative to different surrounding bodies.

A body in motion cannot be at rest (i.e., it cannot touch the same part of space twice in succession).  A body in motion can never be in two places at once.  A body in motion can never touch a later place without first having passed over each of the earlier places in sequence.  Granting these principles, and granting that time is not infinitely divisible, it follows that in an indivisible moment of time, if the body is really moving, it will have to move from exactly one place to one other, no more (since then it is in two places at once) and no less (since then it is at rest and not in motion).  But then it simply cannot have different relative motions.  If it moves from touching one places to touching another on its North side, it cannot move over any more or any less places on its South side.  The only way this could make sense is if both the places and the times of its motion are infinitely divisible (allowing for there to be two half times at which it is successively at two half intervals on the slower side while in the first half time it is at one full interval on the faster side).  But time at least is not infinitely divisible, as has already been argued. (610-l-r)

    5.     What are the only three conceivable types of composition of extension?

Extension might be composed of extensionless points, of extended but indivisible parts, or of parts that are always further divisible. (610-r)

    6.     Why can extension not be composed of mathematical points?

Because mathematical points have 0 extension and 0 added to 0, however many times, does not add up to any finite quantity.  So no extension can arise from the aggregation of points. (610-r)

    7.     Why can extension not be composed of extended but indivisible atoms?

Because a body cannot be in two places at the same time.  Consequently, the only way it can take up more than a point and so be extended is if it has different parts, one in the one place and one in the other.  But if the parts are in different places they are outside of one another, which makes them not the same beings as one another.  But then the thing must be divisible, at least in principle if not in fact because it is composed of distinct beings, and distinct beings are always separable. (610-r)

    8.     What is the “sophism” (fallacy or logical error) in the argument that if extension is not composed of indivisibles (mathematical points or extended but indivisible atoms) then it must be infinitely divisible?

The sophism of insufficient enumeration of parts or alternatives.  If you are going to argue that because A and B cannot be the case then C must be, then it had better be that A, B, and C, are all the alternatives that there are.  If there is a further alternative that you have ignored, then from the fact that A and B are not the case, it does not follow that C must be the case.  The neglected alternative may instead be the case.  While it might seem like composition by indivisibles (of two different sorts) and composition by divisible are the only alternatives there is in fact a further one: no composition by anything.  That is the alternative negelected here.  (611-r-l)

    9.     What makes the hypothesis of infinite divisibility the strongest of the three?

It quibbles best.  (611-l)  When speaking of infinity we can take refuge in the claim that the infinite is naturally incomprehensible to human minds and use this claim to cover over the inadequacies in our argument (610r), and we can take further advantage of the obscurity of the subject to draw unintelligible distinctions that enable us to triumph in public disputation. (611-l)

10.     What makes it as clear and evident as the Sun that matter could not be infinitely divisible?

If matter were infinitely divisible the tiniest imaginable object would have to contain infinitely many parts, each of which is of non-0 extension (for 0’s would add up to nothing).  And that is a patent impossibility.  Infinitely many non-0 parts add up to something infinitely large, not anything of any finite extent, much less something arbitrarily small. (611-1-r)

11.     What is required for an extended substance to exist?  Why can this requirement not be met if space is infinitely divisible?

Contact of the parts of the substance with one another.  If the parts are not in contact, you do not have one extended substance but many separated by empty space.  But then the question recurs about the extension of those many substances.  If the many substances have zero extension then they are nothing and do not exist. If they have some extension they are divisible into parts, but the parts must be in contact with one another, otherwise they once again do not make up one, extended substance.  The requirement for contact cannot be met in an infinitely divisible space because however close you take two parts to be to one another, there would have to be an infinity of other spaces intervening between them. (611-r)

12.     Why can extension exist only in the mind?

Because were it to exist in reality there would have to be contact of the parts making up the extended thing and that is impossible as has just been shown.  So, just as we say that lines are merely ideal because it is impossible to have something that has length but no breadth, so we must say that extension is merely ideal because it is impossible to have something that takes up space and yet does not have contiguous parts. (611-r)

13.     What conclusion did Bayle draw from the fact that a cannon ball, coated with paint and rolled along a table, will draw a line of paint on the table?

That the cannon ball must touch the table, notwithstanding what was proven earlier about the impossibility of the immediate contact of objects.  However, this touching would have to involve two different bodies being in two different places at the same time.  This is because, in an infinitely divisible space, there can be no such thing as two immediately adjacent points.  Any points that are adjacent must be separated by an infinity of other points.  The only way that two points could touch, therefore, is if they coexist in the same place.  But if space is infinitely divisible, any “point” of the cannon ball that coexists in the same place as a “point” of the table must itself be infinitely divisible.  So an infinite number of table parts and cannonball parts must coexist in the same place.  Though this conclusion is entirely opposed to the earlier one, that contact of bodies is impossible, both this conclusion and the other one follow with equal force from the evidence, thus further demonstrating the unintelligibility of infinite divisibility, which leads to such singly paradoxical and mutually inconsistent results. (611-r – 612-l)

14.     Would Bayle have accepted Locke’s distinction between type (i) ideas of the primary qualities of bodies and type (ii) ideas of the sensible qualities that bodies cause us to feel in virtue of the real constitution of their insensibly small parts?

No.  Locke based the distinction on the claim that our type (i) ideas are resemblances of qualities in bodies whereas our type (ii) ideas are not.  But Bayle pointed out that all the same arguments that are used to show that our type (ii) ideas are not resemblances of any quality in bodies apply just as well to the primary qualities of size, shape, and extension. (612-l)

15.     Why are geometrical proofs of infinite divisibility equally effective at disproving infinite divisibility?

The proofs work by showing that for every point on a longer line (the diagonal of a square or the circumference of the larger of two concentric circles) there must be a point on a shorter line.  (Imagine radii drawn from the larger circle to the center and apply the principles that two distinct points determine a unique straight line and that no two distinct straight lines can intersect at more than one point.  This proves that each radius must cut the smaller circle at a unique point.)  Since the longer line can be made arbitrarily long (the larger circle can be arbitrarily large) it follows that the shorter line must consist of infinitely many parts.  The trouble with this line of argument is that it leads to the untoward consequence that the longer line and the shorter one must both be of the same length, since they both consist of equal numbers of parts. (612-l)

16.     Give two reasons why infinite divisibility forbids the beginning of motion.  Give one why a ball rolling down an inclined table could never roll off the edge of the table.

First, because however slowly a body moves, if it moves and is not at rest it must be in two places at once.  Second, because before it can get anywhere at all, it has to cross an infinite number of places in succession, without taking any of them more than one at a time, since there are always infinitely many points between any two given points.  This means that it will never be able to finish the job of getting the least bit on down the line.  The rolling ball will never drop of the edge of the table for a similar reason: wherever it is, there will be infinitely many places between it and the edge of the table, each of which must be passed over one at a time, requiring infinitely many times to reach the edge. (613-r)

17.     Why could one body not move faster than another?  Why could we not suppose that when one body moves faster than another that the slower one stops in its motion for longer or shorter intervals?

Because if motion exists it can neither be faster nor slower than one place at a time.  If the body moves more than one place at a time it is in two places at once, which is impossible.  If it moves less it is not moving at all.  The possibility of motions being faster or slower because the apparently slower body really does rest cannot account for the motion of the parts of wheels.  On wheels the parts on the circumference move much more quickly than the parts towards the center.  But if this were accounted for by saying that the center parts rest while the circumferential ones are in motion, it would follow that wheels would have to be distorted by motion.  Their spokes would have to stretch and bend as the outer parts moved while the inner parts rested.  Yet we observe no such thing. (613-r – 614-l)

18.     Given that motion does in fact undeniably exist, what is the point of giving arguments to prove that it does not?

It shows that human reason is unable to explain the most evident and undeniable things, as that there is motion of extension.  Consequently, the mere fact that we cannot understanding something is no proof that it might be false.  This extends to the mysteries of revealed religion. (614-l)

 

30

Berkeley, Principles Introduction

(Abstract Ideas)

 

    1.     What is the chief cause of those obstacles and difficulties that have so far prevented us from making any progress in philosophy?

False principles, wrongly insisted upon.  And among these, particularly the doctrine that the mind has a power of abstracting ideas. (Introduction §§4 and 6)

    2.     What is our “most abstract idea of extension” (Introduction 8) an idea of?

Just of the taking up of some space, without any specification of how much space is taken up or what shape this space taken up is or what it is that takes up the space.

    3.     What is the one sense in which Berkeley thought it is possible to abstract?

The sense of dividing things into their spatial or temporal parts and considering those parts separately from their surroundings.  (§10)

    4.     What are the “proper acceptations of abstraction” (i.e. the senses in which this ability has been understood according to the tradition Berkeley is attacking)?

The ability to form isolated and separate ideas of qualities that cannot in fact exist on their own, and the ability to form separate and isolated ideas just of those qualities that a number of different objects share in common. (§10)

    5.     What are the two arguments against the traditional conception of abstraction that Berkeley had to offer in Introduction 10?

(i) That he personally found it psychologically impossible, upon introspection, to “imagine,” “consider by itself abstracted or separated,” “frame,” “conceive,” or “form” ideas of individual qualities abstracted from concomitant qualities, or the essences of kinds abstracted from all particularizing features.  (ii) That the generality of simple, illiterate people make no claim to have such ideas.

    6.     What was Locke’s reason for claiming that human beings are able to form abstract ideas?

We use general terms, and Locke maintained that this indicates that we must have formed abstract ideas of sorts or kinds for the terms to refer to. (§11)

    7.     Why did Berkeley find this reason to be inadequate?

Just because we use general terms, it does not follow that they must refer to abstract ideas.  The terms could instead be used to refer to classes of resembling particulars. (§11)

    8.     How can an idea be general without being abstract?

By being made to serve as a sign for a kind of particular, much as a particular black, one-inch long line segment on a particular piece of paper can serve as a sign for any segment whatsoever. (§12)

    9.     What is the argument against the traditional conception of abstraction that Berkeley had to offer in Introduction 13?

That it is impossible to form abstract ideas because the ideas would have to exhibit contradictory qualities.

10.     What is the erroneous supposition about the nature of language that lies at the root of the supposition that we have abstract ideas?

The supposition that each name in a language can only refer to one particular idea. (§18)

 

30a

Berkeley, Three Dialogues I, pp. 171-187

(Naïve Realism)

 

    1.     What is the cause of scepticism, according to Philonous?  That is, what is the cause of “professing an entire ignorance of all things” and of “notions as are repugnant” to “the plain dictates of nature and common sense?”

Believing in the existence of what philosophers call “material substance.” (172)

    2.     In what sense might someone who denies that matter exists be considered a sceptic, according to Hylas?

Not the sense in which to be a sceptic is to doubt everything, but the sense in which to be a sceptic is to deny the reality and truth of things. (173)

    3.     What “things” is someone who denies the real existence of sensible things denying to exist?  Another way to ask this question is, “what things are immediately perceived by the senses?”

Sensible qualities or combinations of sensible qualities, where by “sensible qualities” we mean light, colour, figure, sounds, tastes, odours, and tangible qualities. (175)

    4.     According to Hylas, do sensible things exist only when they are perceived, or do they exist whether we perceive them or not?

They exist whether we perceive them or not. (175)

    5.     What is wrong with supposing that whatever degree of heat we perceive by sense must exist in the object that occasions our perception?

A very great degree of heat is pain, but pain only exists in sentient creatures, not in material substances in general (particularly not in fire). (176)

    6.     Is there any vehement sensation that can be conceived apart from (i.e., in abstraction from) conceiving pain, or any pain that can be conceived in general apart from any particular vehement sensation?

Both Hylas and Philonous agree that there is not. (176-77)

    7.     Why could a very great degree of heat not have any real being, according to Hylas?

Because it is no different from pain and so cannot exist outside of the mind of some sentient creature as a quality of mind-independent material substances. (177)

    8.     What is wrong with insisting that moderate degrees of heat and cold are not forms of pleasure and pain, but instead qualities that could exist unperceived in material substances?  (Grant, for the sake of argument, that moderate degrees of heat and cold are not, in fact, pleasant or uncomfortable.)

The same object can cause us to experience very different degrees of moderate heat and cold at the same time.  Since opposed degrees of the same quality cannot exist in the same object at the same time, and so must exist only in the minds of sentient creatures. (178-79)

    9.     Fill in the blank: Heat is to fire as ____ is to the prick of a pin.  What should we conclude from this?

Heat is to fire as pain is to the prick of a pin, from which we should conclude that heat is no more a quality in fire than pain is a quality in the pin.

10.     What is wrong with maintaining that there are two kinds of heat and cold and taste and smell, one perceived by us that is experienced as being pleasant or unpleasant, and another existing unperceived as a quality in material substances?

By definition, the second kind of heat, cold, taste, and smell are not immediately perceived by the senses.  But the question at hand is whether the things immediately perceived by the senses exist independently of being perceived. (180)  Recall that at 174 Hylas declared that he takes sensible things to be things immediately by the senses, not things inferred from sensory experience.  And at 175 he declared first, that the things immediately perceived by the senses are sensible qualities, and second, that these things exist independently of being perceived.  So Hylas, by his own admissions, is compelled to accept that he means to talk about heat, cold, taste, and smell as they are immediately perceived by us, and not about some other sort of qualities not immediately perceived by us.

11.     Give two reasons why we should not say that sugar is sweet.

First, sweet tastes are pleasant, which is to say that they are particular forms the feeling of pleasure can take on.  But feelings of pleasure exist only in the minds of sentient creatures and not unperceived in insentient bodies like sugar.  Second, the same amount sugar can taste sickeningly sweet to one person and not sweet enough to another.  Since it can’t be both at once, this means that the tastes must be in the persons and not in the sugar.

12.     Why should sound be said to be in the air rather than in the body that makes the sound?

Because nothing makes a sound in a vacuum. (181)

13.     What exactly is sound as it is in the air?  What, in contrast, is sound in “the common acceptation of the word?”  Which of these two sorts of “sound” is heard?  Which could be only seen or felt and why could this sort of sound not be heard but only be seen or felt?

Sound as it is in the air is a certain vibratory or undulating motion of the air.  Sound in the common acceptation of the word is a sensation that exists only in the mind of a sentient creature and only when perceived.  Only sounds in the common acceptation are heard.  Since sounds in the air are motions, and we don’t hear motions, sounds in the air can only be detected by those senses suited to detecting alterations of place, namely vision and touch. (182)

14.     What is wrong with saying that we see colours “on” objects, or that corporeal substances have colours “inhering in” them, or that [immediately] visible objects have colours “in” them?  Try to identify two things.

First, this language draws a distinction between immediately visible objects and their colours, which are conceived to be qualities that those objects have painted on their surfaces, so that same object might change colour.  But all that we immediately perceive by vision is the colour, not the object it is “on” or “in.”  So, in strictness of speech, we should not say that we immediately see things or substances or objects, but just that we see visual sensible qualities (colours) or bundles of visual sensible qualities. (183)  Second, even if we allow that we see objects as well as colours, not all objects have the colours on or in them that we see to be on or in them.  For example, the brilliant red and purple clouds we see at sunrise are not on the clouds, which are dark mist. (184)

15.     Why should we conclude that all colours whatsoever are only “apparent” in the sense in which the colours on the clouds at sunrise are only “apparent” and not really in the clouds?  Try to give two reasons.

First, because what makes colours merely apparent is that they are seen at some distance rather than up close, and any object, viewed through a microscope, will exhibit different colours, and yet different ones at different magnifications.  So all the naked-eye colours are “seen at a distance” in the same way that the colours on the clouds are. (184)  Second, because tiny animals can be expected to have tiny eyes which would give them a microscopic view.  These animals would see the same objects we do as having different colours.  Similarly, we know when we have jaundice that the change in the colour of the fluid of the eye makes everything look yellow and this is a reason to think that animals that are differently constituted than we are, and that have different sorts of eyes, would experience an object to have a different colour than we experience it to have.  Since objects can’t have different colours at the same time, it is reasonable to conclude that the colours exist only in sentient creatures.   As the microscopic case suggests, even if there are some animals that see colours the objects really and truly have, we are not most likely to be those animals. (185)

16.     What is wrong with saying that colours are in the air rather than on or in visible objects (or, why is it no better to say this than to say that they are on or in visible objects)?  Why should it follow that if colours are in the air they are “invisible” to the eye?  (Hint: the answer here is similar to #13.  Explain what the difference is between colours as they are in the air and colours as they are immediately perceived by us and comment on what follows from this.)

Colours in the air would be motions of the particles, or perhaps wave-like impulses transmitted through some thin, fluid substance.  But we don’t immediately perceive these motions.  It is a question for scientific research whether light is a particle or a wave, and it would not be a question if we saw which it was.  Neither would it be a question which colour has the longer or the shorter wavelength, as we would just see it.  But if we don’t see these colours at all then we certainly don’t immediately perceive them, and the question all along has been who denies the “reality and truth” of sensible things, taken as the sensible qualities we immediately perceive.  It has turned out that it is Hylas who does this, and that he does it because he wants to maintain that these sensible things exist independently of being perceived in material substances.  Hylas has been forced to deny the reality and truth of any such things in material substances.  Philonous, in contrast, who always affirmed that sensible qualities exist in minds can say that he has not denied anything.  And where the cases of sound and colour are concerned, he can claim that common sense, vulgar notions, and ordinary language are on his side, because they all take the colours and sounds we perceive to be sensations in us and not motions in material substances.

 

31

Berkeley, Principles 1-24

(Immaterialism)

 

    1.     What are the objects of human knowledge?

Ideas — either of sensation, reflection or imagination. (Principles §1)

    2.     Is there anything said by Berkeley in Principles 1 that Locke would have disagreed with?

Yes.  While the account of the objects of human knowledge being confined to ideas of sensation, reflection, and imagination is exactly the same as Locke’s (Berkeley’s remarks about extra-ideational sources of knowledge are not made here), Berkeley went on to claim that sensible things or bodies are just collections of ideas, whereas Locke wanted to claim that some of our ideas are resemblances of primary qualities of mind-independent external substances.

    3.     What is required in order for an idea to exist?

It must be perceived by someone.  Note that in conjunction with the answer to #1, this entails that the objects of human knowledge can exist only when perceived. (§§2-3)

    4.     What do I really mean when I say that something I am not now in a position to perceive exists?

That were I to position myself differently, I would get ideas of it. (§3)

    5.     What are the limits on my power of abstraction?

I can only abstract from one another those things which are actually or could possibly be perceived apart from one another.  Since I cannot perceive colour without some shape or shape without some visible or tangible quality, ideas of pure colours, pure heat and pure space cannot be abstracted from one another.  Since I cannot perceive a body without some sensation, the idea of the body and the idea of the sensation cannot be abstracted from one another.  And since I cannot perceive a sensation without thinking it to be perceived by a mind, the idea of a sensation and the idea of being perceived cannot be abstracted from one another. (§5)

    6.     Why should the fact that extension in general (i.e., Cartesian intelligible extension like that the understanding finds in the wax) is inconceivable unless it is supposed to have some specific shape, size and velocity entail that extension in general cannot exist outside of the mind?

Because specific sizes, shapes and velocities are relative to the perceiver.  The same object will appear to be differently shaped, sized and moving depending on how big or small the perceiver is, how the perceiver’s sense organs work, and how the perceiver is positioned.  But if the size, shape and velocity can vary without any variation in the object, then these things must be ideas existing in the mind of the perceiver.  If extension in general cannot be separated from these things, then it, too, cannot exist anywhere but in the mind.  There are therefore two “inseparability” arguments for the mind-dependence of extension to be found in Berkeley: the one described in the lecture and in §10, which appeals to the impossibility of abstracting extension from colour and temperature and to the generally agreed upon fact that the latter exist only in the mind, and the other, described in §11 and just now, which appeals to the impossibility of abstracting extension from specific shapes, sizes and motions, and to the perceptual relativity of shape, size, and motion. (§11)

    7.     Why should we suppose that neither sense nor reason informs us of the existence of solid, extended corpuscles located in space outside of the mind?

Sense does not inform us of these things because all it tells us about are our ideas, not what causes these ideas.  And reason cannot infer that such substances must exist in order to cause our ideas because it is obvious that we are able to get such ideas when it is incontestably the case that there is nothing acting on us to produce them, as when we are dreaming or hallucinating. (§18)

    8.     What is wrong with supposing that some sort of solid, extended substance existing in space outside of the mind and acting on our sense organs when we come into contact with it, might at least provide us with a plausible explanation of why we get the ideas that we do?

It is impossible to explain how something which is capable only of aggregating together in clumps and communicating motion by impact should cause ideas.  So to suppose that this sort of stuff exists does not help to explain the origin of ideas in the least.  You can get as far as it hitting the sense organs and then something happens which it cannot explain and which could, for all you know, be going on even in the absence of the sense organs being hit or even in the absence of any sense organs whatsoever. (§19)

 

 

 

31a

Berkeley Three Dialogues I, pp. 187-207

(Primary Quality Realism; Representational Realism)

 

    1.     Why should the same reasoning employed concerning our perceptions of intermediate degrees of heat and cold, sweetness, and other sensible qualities lead us to conclude that there is no extension or figure in objects?

It was reasoned that since what is pleasantly warm or sweet to one person may be chilly or displeasingly sweet to another that these qualities must be sensations in the mind of the perceiver and not features that exist in objects independently of being perceived.  But what looks small, smooth, and round to one observer may look large, uneven, and angular to another.  Since the object cannot be both at the same time, these qualities, too, must be merely perceptions in the perceiver. (189)

    2.     How is time measured?

By the number of ideas that succeed upon one another within a person’s mind while a certain event is occurring. (190)

    3.     Why may the same motion seem faster to one observer and slower to another?

Because more ideas succeed upon one another in the mind of the one than of the other. (190)

    4.     If extension does not exist outside of the mind, why should it follow that motion, solidity, and gravity cannot exist outside of the mind?

Motion is change of place and so is a modification of extension.  Gravitation is a kind of motion.  Solidity is resistance or pushing back against what tries to move into a space, and so involves both motion and space. (191)

    5.     Why does the fact that sensible qualities cannot exist outside of the mind by itself entail that the primary qualities, especially extension, cannot exist outside of the mind?

Because we cannot conceive extension without conceiving some particular size and shape that is extended, or motion without conceiving some particular extended shape that is in motion.  But we can’t conceive a shape without conceiving edges or boundaries, and we cannot conceive an edge or boundary without employing some sensible quality contrast (such as of black lines on white paper).  Since the one cannot be separated from the other, even thought, it follows that where the one exists, the other must exist as well, and where the one does not exist, the other cannot exist.  But it has been established that the other sensible qualities exist only in the mind.  So the same must hold of extension and motion. (194)

    6.     Granting that there is a distinction to be drawn between sensation considered as “an act of the mind perceiving” and the “immediately perceived” “object of the senses,” what is wrong with saying that the red and yellow of a tulip are not just immediately perceived to be coexistent with (different parts of) the extension of the shape of a tulip, but have a real existence outside of the mind in some unthinking substance?  Why does the distinction between sensations and objects do nothing to avoid this problem?

The problem is that we don’t immediately perceive the unthinking material substance in which the colours inhere.  We just perceive the colours and the shape of the tulip.  Drawing a distinction between the act of the mind in perceiving and the object perceived is of no help here because the unthinking material substance is just not among the objects perceived.  We are still stuck in a situation where all we can talk about is relations between sensible qualities that, as has already been established, exist only insofar as they are perceived and are in no position to declare that we have any form of acquaintance with mind-independent objects. (195)

    7.     What is wrong with saying that anything that is involved in a perception that is additional to the act of the mind in perceiving may exist outside of the mind in an unthinking substance?  Try to identify two things.

First, it is simply false that there is any such thing as an act of the mind that is involved in perception.  This is because, in perceiving, the mind is purely passive or acted upon.  So everything that is involved with perception must be additional to the (non-existent) act of the mind in perceiving.  But then, if we want to maintain that these non-active components may exist outside of the mind in an unthinking substance, we saddle ourselves with the absurd consequence that perceptions as a whole may inhere in unthinking substances.  The dark mist may have perceptions of brilliant red and purple, by this consequence, not just be brilliant red and purple or appear brilliant red and purple to people at a distance watching the sunrise.  As Philonous put it, “does it not follow from your own concessions, that the perception of light and colors, including no action in it, may exist in an unperceiving substance?” (196-7)  Secondly, even if there were an action as well as an object involved in every perception, it would follow that there is an action and an object in pain perceptions.  But then, if the object may exist outside of the mind in an unthinking substance, pain could exist outside the mind in an unthinking substance (197).

    8.     What is wrong with reasoning that even though we can’t understand how the qualities we experience in perception could exist outside of minds, we also can’t conceive how things like whiteness or sweetness could exist on their own, without inhering in some mind-independent material substance that supports their existence?

Since we don’t perceive this material substance, but just the qualities, we must infer it exists by appeal to the qualities.  We are told that the qualities cannot exist on their own but need to be supported by something else as if they were peanut butter and jelly that needs to be held up by some bread spread out underneath them.  The trouble with this is that supporting from underneath is a spatial relation, which presupposes extension.  But extension is itself among the qualities that are said to be in need of “support.”  To evade this, it might be said that the sort of support that is needed is not a “gross literal” support, but that the term is being used metaphorically.  But then it needs to be explained precisely what sort of “support” qualities need, beyond being perceived, in order to be sustained in existence.  And no such explanation is forthcoming. (197-199)

    9.     What is wrong with supposing that even though individual sensible qualities might only exist insofar as they are perceived by minds, multiple qualities might support one another in existing together outside the mind?  Try to identify two things.

First, the earlier arguments of Dialogues I have established that there is no way that qualities can exist outside of the mind, not just that qualities cannot exist in isolation outside of the mind.  And a pre-eminent argument even turned on the inseparability of sensible from primary qualities rather than drawing any conclusion just about their isolated existence. (199-200)  Second (and as a single argument on which Philonous is content to rest his entire case) it is not possible to conceive any quality, or any collection of qualities, that could exist outside of the mind.  The best we can manage to do is conceive sensible qualities or objects existing without conceiving anyone else standing around to perceive them.  But then we ourselves conceive them all along.  So there is nothing our powers of conception can do to establish the existence of things apart from being conceived by any mind, and it is therefore impossible to conceive how sensible things could exist unconceived of. (200)

10.     What is wrong with maintaining that sensible objects must exist outside of the mind because in vision we see them existing at some distance away from us?  Try to identify three things.

First, we have the same visual experiences of light and colours in dreams as we do when awake and yet everyone would agree that when we dream there are no things outside of us.  Since the dreaming and the waking experiences are indistinguishable in what they immediately present to us (light and colours), the one no more proves the existence of outer objects than the other. (201)  Second, the objects that we see continually change as we approach or recede from them so that it is very often the case that when we get up close what we see is nothing like what we saw from a distance.  This means that we cannot properly say that we saw the same thing from a distance that we saw from up close.  We saw quite different things.  What we saw from a distance was not the close object seen from some distance away, but an entirely different visible appearance that only appeared at that distance and that was in fact in us at that distance.  Rather than see objects off in the distance, we see things that only are where we are, but that we have learned to associate with other, quite different visible appearances that we would experience if we were to will certain body motions and wait for a certain time.  Confirmation of this can be gleaned from the widespread opinion that someone born blind and newly made to see would not see anything as if it were distant from them. (201-2)  Third, “distance is a line turned endwise to the eye.”  A line turned endwise to the eye touches the eye in a point.  It makes no difference how long the line is.  It still touches the eye only in a point and so affects it in the same way.  As long as the illumination is sufficient, a firefly, a lighthouse beacon, a meteor, a star, and a supernova all affect the eye in exactly the same way, regardless of their vastly different distances from it.  So it is just wrong that we see objects as if they were set at a distance from us.  We do not see this immediately.  We only judge this on the basis of inference from other information.  Since childhood, the inference has become so quick and easy that we don’t notice it.  But Molyneux’s subject would not draw it, nor do infants.  It is still an inference and not immediate vision. (202)  Fourth, the things we infer to be at a distance from us are all visible figures.  But it has been established that visible figure cannot exist apart from colour, and that colours can only exist in the mind. (202)

11.     What is wrong with maintaining that ideas are pictures, images, resemblances, or signs of other things that exist outside of the mind, so that by immediately perceiving the ideas we are also mediately perceiving the objects they signify?

A picture or sign can only suggest something other than itself to someone who has come to know the object pictured or signified in some other way, such as in a past life or by some other form of knowledge.  More mundanely, objects perceived by one sense can lead us, in virtue of an association based on past experience to think of other things that were perceived by other senses along with them on other past occasions, as when hearing the sound of a coach’s wheels on cobbles leads us to think of a coach and so say that we hear (rather than see) the coach, the hearing being a kind of mediate visual perception by means of sound.  But this only works because we have immediately seen coaches in the past.  We have not immediately seen mind-independent objects.  All of our experience is only of our own perceptions, not of external objects taken to resemble those perceptions.  So we are in no position to consider our perceptions to be signs of any such objects. (203-5)

12.     What is wrong with maintaining that it is at least possible that our ideas may be pictures, images, or resemblances of other things that exist outside of the mind, even if we cannot know for a fact that they are?

Because ideas exist only when they are perceived, they are temporary and fleeting entities that change with every slight body motion or blink of an eye or shift in focus of attention.  Alterations in the state of health also have an influence.  Visual ideas, notably, change with every change in distance, but so likewise do sounds, smells, and heat and cold.  Other changes are brought about by changes in the air or the quality of the light.  But it is thought that material substances remain unaffected by changes in us.  This means that of all the ideas we receive at most only a few and perhaps not any at all would be true copies or images of the supposed external objects.  Even more seriously, all ideas are sensible whereas the supposed material substances are insensible.  But something that is sensible cannot be anything at all like something that is insensible, any more than what is coloured could be like what is invisible, or what is flavourful like what is tasteless.  Nothing can be like a sensation or idea but another sensation or idea. (206)

13.     What principle must be denied in order to escape the scepticism that Hylas is driven into at the close of Dialogues I?

Hylas began by committing himself to three principles: that sensible things are things immediately perceived by the senses; that what is immediately perceived by the senses are the sensible and primary qualities of light, colours, figures, sounds, tastes, odors, and tangible qualities; and that sensible things exist outside of the mind and independently of being perceived.  By the end of Dialogues I Hylas has been forced to deny the “reality and truth” of sensible things, that is forced into what he defined as a second sort of scepticism.  But he has been reduced to this conclusion only because he insisted on maintaining that sensible things exist outside of minds and independently of being perceived, as qualities of material substances.  Had he rejected this principle, he would have been able to avoid scepticism about sensible things by maintaining that the “reality and truth” of those things consists in their existing in minds.  This is Philonous’s non-sceptical, but anti-materialist position.

 

 

32

Berkeley Principles 25-33, 89, 135-156

(Spiritual Realism)

 

    1.     What are the objects of human knowledge?

Ideas — either of sensation, reflection or imagination. (Principles §1)

    2.     Is there anything said by Berkeley in Principles 1 that Locke would have disagreed with?

Yes.  While the account of the objects of human knowledge being confined to ideas of sensation, reflection, and imagination is exactly the same as Locke’s (Berkeley’s remarks about extra-ideational sources of knowledge are not made here), Berkeley went on to claim that sensible things or bodies are just collections of ideas, whereas Locke wanted to claim that some of our ideas are resemblances of primary qualities of mind-independent external substances.

    3.     What is required in order for an idea to exist?

It must be perceived by someone.  Note that in conjunction with the answer to #1, this entails that the objects of human knowledge can exist only when perceived. (§§2-3)

    4.     What do I really mean when I say that something I am not now in a position to perceive exists?

That were I to position myself differently, I would get ideas of it. (§3)

    5.     Why can one idea not be the cause of another?

Berkeley maintained that ideas are “passive and inert,” that is, that they can’t do anything, they can only be something. (§25)

    6.     How many different kinds of substance are there?

Just one: mental substance.  Berkeley thought that material substance is impossible and he did not ever mention any other kind of substance.  Sometimes, however, he divided mental substances into two sub-groups, putting God alone in one group and all other “finite” minds in the other. (§26)

    7.     What does our freedom of will strictly allow us to do, according to Berkeley?

Berkeley made no mention of the will being able to make the body move.  All it is able to do is make ideas come and go.  Since he believed that there is no such thing as material substance, and that all we are is minds with certain collections of ideas in them, among which are some that we refer to as their own bodies, this makes perfect sense.  There is no body to move, for Berkeley.  All that moving the body amounts to is being able, through an act of will, to be able to change your sensory ideas of where the parts of the body are located. (§27)

    8.     What made Berkeley think that our ideas of sense are not produced by ourselves?

The fact that we have no power over them (they come and go independently of what our wills dictate). (§29)

    9.     How did Berkeley distinguish ideas of sense from other ideas?

By their appearance (they are clearer and more distinct, draw our attention more forcibly, and are better able to excite feelings of pleasure and pain, or attraction and aversion), and also by their manner of occurrence (they happen in certain regular patterns or sequences, eg., fire burns and heavy things fall down, and they occur independently of our wills). (§30)

10.     Berkeley did not believe that the law of universal gravitation is a description of a force in bodies that makes them move towards one another.  What did he think this law, and the laws of nature in general are descriptions of?  What is the only “force” in nature, as far as he was concerned?

The law of gravitation is a description of the manner in which God produces ideas of bodies in us from moment to moment.  The laws of nature are in general descriptions of the order in which God produces ideas.  (Since God, being supremely constant, always produces ideas in the same way, these laws are never violated.)  The only force in nature, therefore, is God, who acts by producing ideas of nature in us in accord with certain laws.  (§30)

11.     Did Berkeley follow Locke in believing that the existence of other finite minds must be accepted on faith?

No.  He thought that there is a causal argument that establishes that the existence of other finite minds is at least a likely hypothesis.  Among our ideas of reality are ideas of other human bodies.  And these human bodies appear to be moved by causes which indicate that they are actuated by distinct and separate intelligences.  The most likely way to account for this, according to Berkeley, is to suppose that my ideas of these human bodies are caused by these other intelligences, albeit with God’s concurrence. (§§145, 148)

12.     In what sense do we see God?

By seeing a collection of ordered, regular, magnificent, beautiful, vast, detailed and harmonious ideas of reality, that testify to the ongoing activity of a supremely wise and beneficent agent responsible for creating them.  (§§146-148)

 

33

Hume, Enquiry 4

(Sceptical doubts about our powers of knowledge)

 

    1.     How are propositions expressing a relation between ideas discovered?

Hume said “by the mere operation of thought.”  By this he seems to have meant that all we need to do is think about the two ideas being related, and we should be simply able to see, from comparing them with one another as regards to their content, that they stand in the relation.  Or, if we can’t simply see how they are related, we should at least be able to demonstrate this fact. (Enquiry §4 ¶1)

    2.     In what way is the “evidence” (or evidentness) of a true matter of fact, such as that the sun will rise tomorrow, different from that of a relation of ideas, such as that equals added to equals are equal?

Even though the matter of fact is true, it is not necessarily true.  We can imagine it turning out to be false and the thought of its falsity is not incoherent or self-contradictory.  But we cannot consistently think that equals added to equals are unequal.  So the relation of ideas is not just true, but necessarily true.  Unlike the matter of fact, it could not even possibly be false. (4.2)

    3.     What assures us of the truth of matters of fact?  (Identify three things).

The present testimony of the senses, memory, and causal inference (i.e. inferring past causes from presently sensed or remembered effects, or past, present or future effects from presently sensed or remembered causes). (4.3-4)

    4.     Why would someone who found a watch on a deserted island infer that it had once been inhabited?

Because we presume that there is a connection between our present experience of the watch and the prior existence of inhabitants.  This connection is causal.  We think that the watch must have been created by some person, and that it can only be present on an uninhabited island if some person left it there. (4.4)

    5.     What is it, according to Hume, that leads us to suppose that two different things are related to one another as cause and effect?

Experience that the one is constantly followed by the other. (4.6)

    6.     Why should we think that it is not possible, by simply examining and analyzing a cause, to deduce what its effect will be?  Give two reasons, the second one specific to the case of those causal relations that “have become familiar to us from our first appearance in the world, bear a close analogy to the whole course of nature, and supposedly depend on simple qualities of bodies rather than an unseen microscopic constitution of parts.”

(i) when we see a cause for the first time, we have no idea what effect will result from it until we witness that effect occurring.  Similarly for witnessing an effect and not knowing what its cause was.  The implication is that it is only experience of the effect actually following upon the cause that teaches us of the connection between the two, not deduction of the one from the other. (4.6-7)  (ii) Cause and effect are two different things, not one and the same thing.  But where two different things are concerned, the affirmation of the existence of the one and the denial of the existence of the other can never amount to a contradiction.  To say P exists and P does not exist is a contradiction and impossible.  But to say C (say, a cause of some kind) exists and E (say, an effect of some kind) does not exist can never make a contradiction.  But if there can be no contradiction in having C and not having (or coming to have) E, then the existence of E can never be deduced from that of C by deductive reasoning.  The only way to discover the connection is by experience and not by analysis and deduction. (4.11).  Hume later (4.20) added a third reason.  It seems that we never infer the existence of a causal connection from just one case, but usually require a number of “experiments” before we come to accept it (any exceptions are drawn under circumstances that very closely resemble those of causal relations we already have come to trust).  But if the connection between cause and effect were deduced by reason alone, we ought to know it after just one occurrence.  Later occurrences merely repeat the information given in the first one, they do not add to it.  This is an indication, therefore, that we do not deduce the effect from the cause or vice versa, but from the experience of frequent, regular conjunction between two events.

    7.     What is wrong with saying that someone who understands the laws governing such things as elasticity, gravitation, cohesion, and impact might be able to tell what effects some causes will have without having to rely on experience?

Because it is only through experience that they learn that certain bodies return to their previous shape after distortion, that others stick together in certain ways, that all bodies gravitate toward one another, and that motion is transmitted upon impact.  So anyone who relies on these principles in predicting what will happen next is still drawing inferences from past experience. (4.11-12)

    8.     What is wrong with saying that we learn about the connection between a cause and its effect by experience?

It does not tell us how experience leads us to this conclusion. (4.14)

    9.     What is the “negative” thesis Hume proposed to establish in Enquiry IV.ii?

That there is no reasoning or process of understanding (by which, as becomes clear later, he means any intuitive or demonstrative relation) that leads us from our experience that one type of object is regularly followed or preceded by another type to the conclusion that the one is the cause or the effect of the other. (4.15)

10.     What does past experience directly and certainly inform us of?  What can it not inform us of?

It informs us of what happened in the past (for instance, that one type of object has always preceded or followed another in the past).  It does not inform us of what will happen in the future (for instance, the objects will continue to be so related in the future). (4.16)

11.     Did Hume believe that, from the proposition that an object has always been followed by a certain effect in the past, we may justly infer that similar objects will continue to be followed by similar effects in the future?

Yes.  He just did not think that this inference can be justified by intuition or demonstration.  (4.16)

12.     Did Hume believe that we do in fact always draw the inference described in the previous question?

Yes.  (4.16)

13.     Did Hume believe that the inference is justified by intuitive or demonstrative reasoning?

No.  (4.16)

14.     Why can there be no demonstrative argument that allows us to take the premise that a cause has led to a certain effect in the past to entail the conclusion that similar causes must lead to similar effects in the future?

Because the course of nature could change (and there is no contradiction in this possibility. (4.18)

15.     What is wrong with arguing that since a cause has led to a certain effect in the past, and since the future generally resembles the past, then the cause will likely continue to lead to the effect in the future?

This begs the question.  Why should we suppose that the fact that things have been a certain way in the past sets any rule for how they will continue to be in the future?  This is precisely what is at issue and it is only if we presuppose that it is not at issue and that the future must resemble the past that the argument of this question can have any force with us. (4.21)

16.     What conclusion did Hume draw from the fact that peasants and children and even animals are able to do causal reasoning?

That causal reasoning cannot be based on any difficult, obscure or sophisticated thought process. (4.23)

 

34

Hume Enquiry 5.1-9, 9

(Naturalism)

 

    1.     What is the one passion that is not frustrated by the sceptical philosophy?

The love of truth. (Enquiry 5.1)

    2.     Why do we not need to be afraid that sceptical doubts will render us incapable of making decisions about how to act in common life?

Because our natural instincts will induce us to act even if the sceptical philosophy shows us that we have no rational justification for choosing to act as we do. (5.2)

    3.     Why would a rational being, brought suddenly into this world, not at first be able to reach the idea of cause and effect?

Because all the being would see is one event following another.  It would not see any connecting link between events that pulls one after the other, and it could not justly infer that simply because one event has occurred after another on one occasion in the past that therefore the first caused the second. (5.3)

    4.     What is the consequence of this being’s observing events of a certain type to always be followed by events of another type?

It supposes that the existence of the one implies the existence of the other. (5.4)

    5.     What is the principle that induces us to infer the existence of one object from the appearance of another?

The fact that we are so constituted that the repetition of a particular activity induces us to further repeat that activity.  In other words, the fact that we are creatures of habit. We have habits of thought as well as habits of action.  So when we have been trained by experience to see two things in connection, and we subsequently see one of them, we cannot help but believe in the other as well.  (5.5)

    6.     What can we say about what ultimately causes us to develop habits?

Nothing.  All we are in a position to declare is that when a certain sequence of events has been repeatedly observed to take place in the past, the appearance of one of those events will lead us to habitually think of the others and suppose them to exist.  But we have no idea why witnessing a repetition should have this effect on us.  All we know is that this effect does regularly arise in us as a consequence of having repeatedly witnessed a certain sequence of events. (5.5)

    7.     What makes the hypothesis that we are determined by custom to infer causes from effects superior to the hypothesis that we are determined by reason to do so?

When we infer causes from effects, we will often hesitate to infer a causal connection from just one experience of the cause being followed by its effect.  We typically demand evidence of a repeated and constant conjunction between the two types of events.  This is a feature of our thought that cannot be explained by supposing that the inference depends on reasoning, that is, on intuiting the content of ideas, discerning relations between ideas given their intuited content, and demonstrating consequences based on our intuitions of these relations.  Repetition of the same ideas over and over again does not add anything to their content and so cannot enable us to draw any conclusion by means of reasoning that we could not draw the first time we witnessed the ideas, prior to any repetition.  But if we suppose that causal inference is due to custom, then that explains why repetition has such an influence on us.  The repetition is what establishes the custom. (5.5)

    8.     What two things are necessary if we are to believe in the existence of an object that we are not now perceiving?

(i) We have to have an impression of some other object given to us by our senses or an idea of it delivered by memory, and (ii) we have to have in the past experienced some customary conjunction between this other object and the object that we believe to exist. (5.7)

    9.     What is it that ensures that these two things will necessarily and unavoidably produce the belief?

Our natural instincts (as opposed to our reasoning ability). (5.8)

10.     How did Hume propose to confirm his theory concerning the foundation of our inferences from experience in Enquiry IX?

By showing that it accounts for how animals come by their beliefs in the existence of unperceived objects.  Since animals bear a degree of analogy to human beings, showing that something is the case for animals supports the likelihood that it is the case for human beings as well, just as showing that blood circulates in gorillas and chimpanzees establishes a likelihood that it does in human beings as well. (9.1)

11.     What convinced Hume that animals get their knowledge of the nature of fire, water, earth, stones, heights, depths, etc. from experience rather than from innate instincts?

Young animals appear not to have this knowledge and seem only to acquire it through experiencing the appropriate objects. (9.2: 70)  Also because animals may be trained to do or not do things by experience of rewards and punishments, even if those things are contrary to their natural instincts. (9.3)

12.     What convinced Hume that animals do not get their knowledge of unperceived objects by reasoning that like effects will always follow like causes, or that the course of nature will not change?

They don’t appear to be smart enough to formulate such arguments. (9.5)

13.     Why would “nature” (i.e. a wise designer) have preferred to make causal inference depend on custom rather than reasoning?

Because reasoning is difficult to do and often fails us because we do it too slowly or improperly.  The business of drawing causal inferences is too important for everyday life, and needs to be done too quickly to be trusted to such a slow and fallible operation as reasoning.  Custom is quicker, broader, and easier in its application. (9.5)

14.     If custom is the cause of causal inference, how is it that we can sometimes draw inferences from just one experiment?

When we have lived for a while and gained a broad experience of many different sorts of things, we become accustomed to expect that more or less the same thing that has happened in certain circumstances in the past will happen in those circumstances in the future.  That is, we form a sort of general habit.  In contrast to our specific habits, which lead us to associate some specific type of thing with some specific other type of thing (e.g., stones with falling, fire with burning, water with suffocating, etc.) this general habit leads us to associate any thing in general with whatever has once been observed to follow from that thing.  We are led to form this habit because, by and large, that is just what we experience.  Nature is generally uniform in its operations, and it is less likely that, when the same circumstances recur, something different will happen than that the same sort of thing will happen again.  So, the short answer is that a broad and general experience of an underlying uniformity in nature leads us to form this habit. (Note u)

15.     How did Hume distinguish what animals believe by instinct from what they learn from experience?

Instinctive beliefs lead animals to do things that much exceed the degree of intelligence we would be inclined to ascribe to them based on a broad survey of what they are able to learn.  Moreover, it is not altered by experience. (9.6)

16.     Why should we think that there is nothing unique or special about animal instincts?

Because our own tendency to draw inferences based on analogy to what we have witnessed in the past is itself based merely on an animal instinct. (9.6)

 

35

Hume, Enquiry 2, 3.1-3, 5.10-22

(Belief)

 

    1.     What are impressions?

All the more lively perceptions of the mind. (Enquiry §2 ¶3)

    2.     In what sense is the imagination confined within narrow limits?

It must work with the materials supplied to us by our senses and experience and cannot originate any absolutely new simple ideas. (2.4)

    3.     Why does the idea of God not falsify Hume’s claim that all of our ideas are composed of materials originally obtained from impressions?

Unlike Descartes, Hume thought that this idea can be created by simply taking impressions of our mental, moral, and physical capacities and multiplying them. (2.6)

    4.     What significance did Hume attach to the fact that a blind person can form no idea of colours?

It implies that we do not have the ability to create ideas that do not copy impressions we have previously received. (2.7)

    5.     How did Hume propose to eliminate jargon from metaphysics?

By investigating what the words employed in metaphysical disputes stand for.  Metaphysical terms should stand for ideas, and all ideas must have been copied from impressions.  If we can’t identify the original impressions, we can dismiss the terms as meaningless. (2.9)

    6.     For each of the following identify the associative principle that leads the mind from thinking of the first idea to thinking of the second.

a.       the idea of the book leads us to remember its author causality (effect to cause)

b.      The idea of fire leads us to think of the sun resemblance

c.       the idea of fire leads us to think of melting wax causality (cause to effect)

d.      the idea of Texas leads us to think of Mexico contiguity (in space)

e.       the idea of the ides of March leads us to think of Julius Caesar contiguity (in time, as this was the day on which Caesar was assassinated)

    7.     What is the difference between fiction and belief?

When we believe, there is some sentiment that attaches itself to the idea of what we believe.  This sentiment must be excited by natural causes and is not within our control. (5.11)

    8.     Why does belief have nothing to do with the peculiar nature or order of ideas?

Because if it did, the imagination, which can alter the content and order of ideas as it sees fit, could produce belief at will, and this is not the case. (5.12)

    9.     Identify the two factors responsible for getting a lively idea of an absent friend from a picture.

There must be a resemblance between the picture and the friend, and the picture has to be actually seen or remembered. (5.15)

10.     What significance did Hume attach to Roman Catholic claims that performing rituals before images and statues enlivens their faith?

He considered this to be evidence that the relation of resemblance can enliven belief in an object — or at least draw our attention to the resembled object more readily by communicating vivacity from a presently sensed object (the statue) to a resembling idea (the saints).  “Sensible objects, have always a greater influence on the fancy than any other; and this influence they readily convey to those ideas . . . which they resemble.” (5.16)

11.     Why do our ideas of home become more lively as we get closer to it?

Because we receive impressions of the contiguous regions.  A thought of the contiguous region would not produce a lively idea, though it would lead us to think of home.  But an actual impression produces a lively idea.  (5.17)

12.     Explain the analogy between the effects of causation and those of resemblance and contiguity on our beliefs.

Just as, when you have an impression, that impression both brings to mind any ideas you may have that resemble it or are of objects contiguous to it, and enlivens those ideas, so, when you have an impression, that impression both brings to mind ideas of its effects and its causes and creates a belief in the past or impending existence of those causes and effects. (5.18)

13.     What accounts for the fact that there is a pre-established harmony between the course of nature and the succession of our ideas?

The fact that we are naturally so constituted as to habitually believe objects to continue to occur in succession if they have customarily occurred in that way in the past. (5.20)

14.     Why is it better that our abilities to infer causes from effects and effects from causes should be due to “some instinct or mechanical tendency” rather than to reason?

Reason takes years to develop, is not as infallible in its working and takes longer to figure out what to do. (5.22)

 

36a

Hume Enquiry 6

(Probability)

 

    1.     Does anything ever happen by chance?

No. (Enquiry 6.1)

    2.     Why do we treat certain events as if they were the products of chance?

Because our ignorance of the true cause of those events leaves with no choice but to take the circumstances surrounding their past occurrences as likely indications of their reoccurrence, in proportion to how often this regularity has been observed in the past. (6.1)

    3.     What is the “very nature” of chance events?

A chance event is one of a number of alternative outcomes that are considered equally capable of occurring in a given circumstance. (6.3)

    4.     What happens when the mind is carried more frequently to one sort of event when surveying the various possible or chance outcomes of a cause, such as throwing a die with a number of faces that concur in having the same number on them?

We believe that event will occur. (6.3)

    5.     What accounts for the “sentiment of belief” that we get when several “views” concur in the same event, i.e., when several of the chance outcomes of a cause are the same?

That is just how we are made.  Hume attributed the origin of the belief to an “inexplicable contrivance of nature.” (6.3)

    6.     How do “philosophers” account for the failure of causes to produce their usual effects?

By appeal to the operation of hidden causes (typically, some small circumstance that needs to be present or absent for the cause to be followed by its effect but that typically goes unnoticed). (6.4)

    7.     In cases where a cause has not always been observed to be followed by the same type of event, what do we imagine happening after the cause, when we witness it again in the future?

We imagine all the different sorts of events that have been observed to follow from that cause in the past.  But we also imagine those events in their proportions.  That is, if one type of event has only been observed to follow from the cause once, we imagine just one of it, where if another type of event has been observed to follow from the cause a hundred times, we imagine one hundred copies of it.  We then believe that event which is imagined most often, with a degree of belief that is proportional to its frequency in the total sample. (6.4)

 

36b

Hume, Enquiry 7

(Necessary Connection)

 

    1.     Which of our ideas are always clear and determinate?  Which are ambiguous, and why?

Those of the mathematical sciences are clear and determinate.  Hume attributed this to the fact that they copy impressions that are given in sensation, but it might be more accurate to specify that they copy impressions of vision and touch, that is, impressions of specifically spatial objects.  Because the parts of space are permanent, it is at least possible to go back to look at spatial things a second time.  Things that exist only in time are not like this.  Once the time has passed, we can’t go back to compare them with other things or check our memories.  Hume thought that those ideas that copy our passions and our impressions of reflection of the operations of our own minds are ambiguous, and it is largely for the reason that they exist only in time.  Though these latter impressions are quite distinct, they are difficult to attend to when they occur and cannot be simply be recreated at will and this makes them hard to contemplate and reflect upon. (7.1)

    2.     What is necessary if we are to discover the precise meaning of obscure terms like “force,” “power,” “energy,” or “necessary connection?”

We need to identify and examine the impression or impressions from which these ideas were first derived. (7.5)

    3.     What do our senses tell us about the operation of causes from viewing any single instance of a causal relation between external objects?

Just that the cause is followed by its effect.  But we do not witness any power in the cause in virtue of which it brings its effect about.  We just see that the effect follows after it. (7.6)

    4.     What significance did Hume attach to the fact that we cannot tell, upon seeing an object for the first time, what its effects will be?

It means that our senses cannot be telling us anything about any power in causes in virtue of which they are enabled to bring about their effects.  For, if we knew of such a thing, we ought to be able to deduce the effect from it and so predict what the effect will be in advance. (7.7)

    5.     What significance did Hume attach to the fact that the qualities of bodies, so far as our senses can detect them, are all complete in themselves?

Since they are complete in themselves, contemplating them can’t tell us about any other thing.  But if a body has powers, those powers are abilities to bring about changes of certain kinds, either in that body itself or in other things.  So they involve a reference to something else (another thing or a changed state of the given thing).  Thus, we cannot hope to deduce what powers a body will have simply by contemplating its sensible qualities. (7.8)

    6.     Why has it been thought that we acquire the idea of power from internal sensation or reflection?

Because we sense in ourselves an ability to move our limbs or make out thoughts come and go through willing it to happen.  In experiencing volition we therefore appear to be experiencing a power. (7.9)

    7.     What do we really know about the relation between our volitions and the motion of our bodies?

Just that certain kinds of volitions are regularly followed by certain kinds of body motions.  But we have no idea of why.  This means that we have no idea of any power in the will that enables it to move the body. (7.10)

    8.     What significance did Hume attach to the observation that a person with a newly paralyzed or amputated limb can have the same feeling of will to move the limb as a healthy person?

That the feeling and the power to move the limb must be two different things (because obviously the feeling doesn’t work in this case to bring about motion). (7.13)

    9.     What does it mean to know a power?

To know what it is in the cause that enables it to bring about a particular effect. (7.17)

10.     What significance did Hume attach to the fact that we are unable to explain how the mind is able to produce ideas upon a command of the will?

That we have no conception of any power in us to create ideas.  Our feeling of our own will when we desire to have a certain thought is not a sensation of a power, but merely a peculiar feeling that is regularly followed by a certain effect (the production of an idea). (7.17)

11.     Why do “many philosophers” (e.g., Malebranche and Berkeley) think it necessary to appeal to the immediate agency of God to explain the occurrence of familiar events when uneducated people only invoke this cause to explain the occurrence of extraordinary, miraculous and supernatural events?

The uneducated think that those events that regularly happen before other events just are the forces or powers responsible for producing those events.  (Even though they have no idea of how the earlier event produces the later one, the fact that the two regularly occur in succession makes their sequence seem so natural that the uneducated think that no special explanation is required, and that is just the way things are.)  However, when they encounter extraordinary events in nature, which by definition do not have any regularly occurring antecedents, they turn to explain them by supposing they were produced by some unseen intelligence.  But philosophers, who have inquired into how causes actually work to bring about their effects, and have found that they cannot identify any force or power in causes that enables them to make their effects happen, have come to see even familiar events as being just as inexplicable and miraculous as supernatural events, and so they have been led to suppose that these “natural” events, too, must all be produced by some unseen intelligence. (7.21)

12.     What is wrong with the approach taken by these philosophers?

It insults the power of God to suppose that he could make the universe so that it would run on its own without constant intervention (7.22: 47); it is simply too extravagant a hypothesis given the evidence that can be cited in its support (7.24: 47-48); and, most significantly, it ignores that the force or power in minds, through their volition, to bring things about is just as inexplicable as any force or power in natural causes to bring about effects (7.25)

13.     What are the possible sources of an impression corresponding to our idea of power that Hume examined over the course of Enquiry VII.i?  What is the one remaining source he still had to examine?

He examined single instances of the operation of one body on another; the operation of the mind on the body; the operation of the mind on its ideas (7.26).  Though he mentioned that there is one remaining source that still needs to be examined at 7.27, he did not identify it.  However, it becomes clear from 7.28 that the source is reflection upon our own passions and sentiments.

14.     What is the difference between observing one single event to follow upon another and observing one species (i.e., one collection of similar events or events of the same type) of event to follow upon another?

In the latter case we suppose that the two events are conjoined as cause and effect whereas in the former we hesitate to do so.  We also suppose in the latter case that the two events are necessarily connected. (7.27)

15.     What is the impression that our idea of power or necessary connection is a copy of?

It is not anything we discover in the cause, but rather a sentiment we experience in our own minds when we contemplate a cause that we have experienced to be frequently followed by its effect in the past: the purely subjective, internal feeling of being impelled by habit to form the idea of the effect.  We confuse this sentiment in our own minds with a property of the cause, and think it is the cause that is bringing the effect about rather than our own minds that are calling up the idea of the effect. (7.28)

16.     What do we really mean when we say that one object is connected with another?

Just that the two have acquired a connection in our thought, not that there is a physical connection discernible between the two.  The connection is only in us, between our thoughts, not in the objects. (7.28)

17.     What is the difference between Hume’s two definitions of cause?  In what way do they both come up short of what we might like?

The first talks about the objects involved in the causal relation (that the cause the one, among two constantly conjoined objects that happens first in the sequence), the second about its influence on the mind (that the cause is what, upon its appearance, determines the mind to think of the effect).  But neither comes close to identifying a force or power in the cause in virtue of which it is enabled to bring the effect about. (7.29)

 

 

37

Hume, Enquiry 8

(Liberty & Necessity)

 

    1.     What does our idea of necessity arise from?

The uniformity, observable in the operations of nature, that is, from the fact that certain sorts of things are regularly observed to be preceded or followed by certain other sorts of things.  (Enquiry §8. ¶5)

    2.     What is our idea of necessity an idea of?

Constant conjunction and a disposition of the mind to draw an inference.  That is, the idea that a thing is necessitated is just the idea that it is of a sort that is regularly preceded by some other sort of thing, and of an impulse felt by the mind to infer the former from the latter on account of this constant conjunction.  So the idea of necessity is not the idea of being made or forced to happen.  It is just the idea of being regularly preceded by something else. (8.6)

    3.     What were Hume’s reasons for saying that all people have always concluded that our voluntary actions and operations of mind are necessitated?  (Find two)

First, that similar human actions are constantly preceded by similar motives, so there is a constant conjunction between motive and action.  Second, that as a matter of fact people cannot resist drawing inferences from a knowledge of motives to anticipated future actions, or from a knowledge of actions to the interpretation of motives for those actions.  Since these are the two components of our idea of necessity, it follows that all people think that human actions are necessitated. (8.7 and 8.16)

    4.     What is the chief use of history?

To discover the constant and universal principles of human nature, that is, what actions can be expected to follow from what passions, and what passions are followed by what actions. (8.7)

    5.     What is the benefit of a long life employed in a variety of occupations and company?

It tells us what actions, expressions, and gestures are preceded by what motives, and so allows us to anticipate people’s actions from a prior knowledge of their motives, even when they try to convince us that they intend to act differently. (8.9)

    6.     What is required for us to be able to see through the tricks of con artists and others who want to deceive us?

That particular human actions be necessitated in the sense of being regularly preceded by particular motives.  If there were no regularity in human behaviour, it would be impossible to predict what anyone would do next, and so impossible to say that someone with a vested interested in an outcome would act to achieve that outcome rather than behave altruistically. (8.9)

    7.     What accounts for the fact that not all people behave in precisely the same manner in the same circumstances?

The diversity of characters, prejudices, and opinions. (8.10)

    8.     Why is the fact that there are some actions that seem to have no regular connection with any known motives not an objection to the thesis that human actions are necessitated?

Because human actions do not exhibit any greater degree of irregularity than is observed in occurrences in inanimate nature, and the irregularity in nature does not induce us to reject causal determinism.  So, by parity of example, it ought not to induce us to accept determinism of human actions either.  In somewhat more detail, there are just as many or more occurrences in inanimate nature that do not appear to us to be the consequence of regularly occurring antecedents.  When we encounter these sorts of things in nature, we do not abandon our belief that events are caused.  Instead, we either think that most events are caused, that causal laws are generally true, and that the anomalies are due to some weaknesses in the causes to always bring about their effect, or else we think that we have simply failed to identify all the circumstances and that a more exact scrutiny of the case will uncover some previously unnoticed regularity.  The former view is the (incorrect) view of the vulgar, whereas the latter view, which is strictly necessitarian, is the view of philosophers and is proven by constant experience of investigating anomalous cases and finding that we do always discover some hidden circumstance, so that there appear to be no irreducibly stochastic occurrences in nature. (8.12-15)

    9.     What is the foundation of morals?

Character and sentiment.  (8.18.  Elsewhere, Hume specified that actions are considered to be morally good or bad — virtuous or vicious, as he put it — depending on the motives people have for performing them.  These motives are always sentiments and sentiments are broadly determined by ingrained character traits.  Some people are quicker to anger, for example.)

10.     Why is it that even though people all believe the doctrine of necessity and rely on it in their anticipations of how others will behave, they are reluctant to acknowledge it in words and instead claim that nothing determines human actions?

All they mean to deny is that there is anything in them that forces them to act as they do.  They deny this because they feel no such force or power.  But they think (wrongly) that there is a force or power in natural causes that makes the effects of those causes come about.  This leads them to suppose that they have a freedom that is not to be found in inanimate nature.  As a matter of fact, however, there is no force or power in natural causes and all there is to necessity is just constant conjunction of antecedent and consequent types of events.  And there is the same sort of constant conjunction between human motives and actions. (8.21)

11.     What is meant by attributing liberty to voluntary actions?

That those actions are consequences of a prior will to perform them (8.23)

12.     What makes actions criminal?

Criminal principles of the mind.  In other words, the motives or reasons people have for performing them.  In themselves even actions that have very bad effects can be innocent if they were not done deliberately. (8.29-30)

13.     Why would denying that human actions are necessitated by motives mean that a person must be as pure and untainted after committing the most horrid crime, as at the first moment of birth?

Because we only consider actions to be evil when done from evil motives.  If you deny that there was a motive that determined the action, you make the agent innocent, just as if they were forced by some external cause to do the action, did the action out of ignorance or accidentally, or did the action out of haste and without premeditation. (8.29)

14.     What opposite interests are the moral sentiments based on?

The interest in the peace and security of society and the interest in public detriment and disturbance.  Moral sentiments of approbation arise when we contemplate personal traits of character that advance the former interest, whereas moral sentiments of disapproval arise when we contemplate personal traits of character that advance the latter interest. (8.35)

15.     How did Hume respond to the objection that insofar as the doctrine of necessity makes God the ultimate cause of all human actions, it follows that no human actions can be blameworthy, because God does nothing without a good and valid reason for doing so?

He claimed that our sentiments of praise and blame are not determined by reflections on the ultimate cause of actions but are instead aroused by the characters and motives of the agents who immediately performed them.  Even if you have an “enlarged view” according to which all the evil in the universe is for the best and those who deliberately do evil are necessitated to have their evil motives, you will still blame those who deliberately do evil.  This is because our minds have been so formed that we naturally feel moral sentiments when contemplating the characters and motives of the agents who performed good or bad actions. (8.35)

16.     How did Hume respond to the objection that insofar as the doctrine of necessity makes God the ultimate cause of all human actions, it makes him responsible for their crimes?

He claimed that it is a mystery which mere human reason is unable to resolve.  This is only a valid answer if it really is a mystery, that is, if the alternative “system” that human actions are not necessitated but freely chosen doesn’t resolve the mystery either.  Hume claimed that it doesn’t because even on the alternative view it is supposed that God knows all (“prescience”) and it is not easy to understand how your actions can be free if God knows thousands of years before you are born that you will do them. (8.36)

 

38

Hume, Enquiry 10

(Miracles)

 

    1.     What was the purpose of the miracles performed by the Saviour?

They are supposed to prove that he was on a mission from God.  Just as an ambassador carries letters of introduction from the government to a foreign country to serve as credentials, so miracles, which only God can perform, serve as signs that a particular person is God’s ambassador.  God is supposed to really be the one working the miracles at the behest of the prophet, to prove the prophet’s mission. (Enquiry §10. ¶1)

    2.     Why did Tillotson say that our evidence for the truth of Christianity is less than our evidence for the truth of our senses?

Because Christianity is ultimately based on the sensory experiences of the Apostles, who purportedly witnessed the miracles that prove that Christ was God.  And a report of someone else’s sensory experiences, handed down by a tradition (and so converted to hearsay) can never be as certain as your own sensory experiences. (10.1)

    3.     Why, according to Tillotson, would it be contrary to the rules of just reasoning to believe in a scriptural doctrine that contradicts sensory experience?

Because it can never be reasonable to accept a conclusion if there is stronger evidence for its opposite (“a weaker evidence can never destroy a stronger”).  But the evidence for a scriptural doctrine can never be stronger than the evidence of one’s own senses (see 2 above). (10.1)

    4.     What is the one condition under which a scriptural doctrine could be accepted even though it contradicts sensory experience?

If God’s grace (i.e., the “immediate operation of the Holy Spirit” bringing something into one’s breast) forcibly compels someone to believe against all reason, in the sort of way Bayle alluded to. (10.1)

    5.     What is the difference between a proof and a probability?

A proof is a causal inference founded on a uniform past experience of a particular cause always being conjoined with a particular effect.  A probability is a causal inference founded on an experience of a particular cause being conjoined with a particular effect in most but not all cases. (10.4)

    6.     How is reasoning from human testimony (i.e. supposing that something is the case because someone has told us that it is the case) like reasoning from effect to cause?

In both cases we are guided by past experience of a constant or regular conjunction between events.  In the former case it is hearing a report and ascertaining that the report is true, in the latter it is between witnessing an object and witnessing its cause or effect. (10.5)

    7.     How do we proceed when we find from past experience that a certain kind of report is not entirely reliable?

We balance the circumstances of the case that are indicative of the truth of the testimony against those that are indicative of its unreliability and we incline to the side that is stronger, but with a degree of certainty proportioned just to the amount by which the evidence in favour of the stronger side exceeds that in favour of the weaker. (10.6)

    8.     List some circumstances that might incline us to repose greater trust in human testimony and some that might lead us to give it less trust.

Greater trust arises if there are a number of independent witness (i.e., witnesses who have not communicated with one another beforehand) all giving the same story, if the witnesses are known to be honest, if they have no interest in the case, if they are expert in the field and were in a position to make clear observations, if there is no chance of their having being deceived, and if they would have a great deal to lose were they discovered in a lie or proven to have been duped.  Lesser trust arises if there are few witnesses, if they communicated with one another in advance, if they contradict themselves or one another, if they have something to gain by testifying in the way that they do, if they are known to be dishonest or have nothing to lose by being detected in a lie, if they have no expertise in the area, were not in a position to make accurate observations, or could easily have been duped, or if they deliver their testimony with too much hesitation or too much confidence.  Other circumstances might be mentioned as well. (10.5, 7)

    9.     Why is testimony to an unusual event regarded as less credible the more unusual the event is?

Because an unusual event is one that our own experience tells us does not normally occur in those circumstances.  Thus, when we hear anyone testify to such an event, their testimony, which ought to make us inclined to believe the event occurred, conflicts with our own experience, which makes us inclined to believe the event likely did not occur.  The more unusual the event, the greater the conflict.  Since conflicting pieces of evidence cancel one another in proportion to their strength, and since the more unlikely the event, the greater the conflict with our own experience, a larger portion of the strength of testimony to very unusual events must be devoted to cancelling the evidence of our experience, and that means less strength is left over to incline us to believe. (10.8)

10.     Why does the testimony of credible witnesses to an unusual event produce a “mutual destruction of belief [in what most likely happened in that case] and authority [i.e. trust in the report of the witnesses]?”

Because, by definition, an unusual event is one that turns out contrary to what most of our experience tells us it should.  This means, therefore, that our experience gives us a strong inclination to suppose that the event turned out in a different way, which is to say that we form a suspicion that the witnesses are either deceived or attempting to deceive us.  If, however, our experience also goes to prove to us that witnesses of that sort are likely to be telling the truth, then the two inclinations cancel one another out, and we are left not knowing whether to distrust our natural assumptions about what most likely happens in that sort of case, or to distrust the witnesses to the unusual event.  If one of these options is even slightly more likely than the other, we will opt for it, though with a great diminution in the degree of our conviction. (10.8)

11.     Why is it that from the very nature of the fact there is always a direct and full proof against the occurrence of any miracle?

Because a “proof,” as Hume defined the term, is just a uniform past experience whereas a miracle is by definition what is contrary to a uniform past experience.  Thus a miracle always has a proof (i.e., a uniform past experience telling against it).  For example, if it is a miracle that a bush burns and is not consumed, this is because all our past experience, without exception, tells us that wood is consumed in fire.  If all our past experience did not show that wood is consumed in fire, then this event would not be miraculous, but merely marvellous.  But if all our past experience does show that wood is consumed in fire, then that past experience constitutes a “proof” against the occurrence of the miracle. (10.12)

12.     What would it take to counterbalance this proof and establish that a miracle has occurred?

It would have to be the case that it would be more likely that events occurred as the witnesses to the miracles described than that they are lying or were duped.  But since the witnesses are reporting the occurrence an event that is contrary to what a uniform past experience tells us should have occurred in those particular circumstances, we already have a proof, from past experience, against the occurrence that they are testifying to.  It is not impossible that we could have a stronger proof of the reliability of the witnesses than of the impossibility of the event, but it would have to be based on something other than just experience of the proportion of times witnesses of that sort have told the truth and of the number of times events of the sort reported have not turned out as reported.  But barring that eventuality the two proofs would cancel one another out, inducing us to doubt both the credibility of the witnesses and the certainty of our past beliefs to an equal extent, so that we would be unsure which was right. (10.13)

13.     Why are we more readily tempted to accept stories that are utterly absurd and miraculous, even though we readily reject any fact that is unusual or incredible in an ordinary degree?

Miraculous events evoke surprise and wonder in us, which are agreeable sentiments that the mind likes to indulge in.  Because of this the mind has what Hume called “a sensible tendency towards belief” in miraculous events.  That is, its natural desire for pleasure pushes it in the direction of believing the miraculous tale (because such belief would increase its sentiments of awe and wonder).  And even if it cannot push us so far as to make us actually believe the event, it makes us want to recount it to others and try to convince them of it (so that we can experience surprise and wonder at second hand, by witnessing it in others). (10.16)

14.     Why do miracles not happen these days?

Miracle stories are still told all the time.  But they are generally exploded because not all people are as easily taken in as they once were. (10.20-23)

15.     Why is it the case that, even if we could demonstrate that an almighty God exists, this would not make it any more likely that miracles occur?

Because just as we have no conception of any force or power in any other cause adequate to allow us to predict ahead of time what its effect will be, so we have no conception of the nature of God adequate for us to determine what God will or will not do.  The only way we can know this is after the fact, through either our own experience or reports of the experiences of others, and this throws us back on having to base our belief in miracles on the testimony of witnesses rather than on a contemplation of the necessary effects of the divine nature. (10.38)

16.     Whose position on the foundation of religious belief did Hume endorse at the close of Enquiry X, Locke’s or Bayle’s?

Bayle’s.  Locke believed that the testimony of witnesses to the occurrence of miracles could give us reason to suppose that a particular revelation had come from God and could so establish a foundation for faith.  But Hume denied that any testimony could be adequate to establish that a miracle has occurred, and maintained that the testimony that has in fact been given for the historical miracles of Christianity falls well short of the standard that would be needed even to lead us to suspend disbelief.  He at least paid lip service to Bayle’s conclusion that belief is accordingly based on nothing more than God’s graciously (or “miraculously” as he put it) compelling some to believe even against all the evidence. (10.41)

 

39

Hume, Enquiry 12

(Scepticism)

 

    1.     What is antecedent scepticism?

The recommendation that we begin our philosophical inquiries by doubting all of our opinions and even all of our cognitive faculties until such time as we have been able to conclusively demonstrate their validity by deduction from absolutely certain first principles. (Enquiry §12 ¶3)

    2.     Why, according to Hume, is Cartesian scepticism incurable?

He maintained that there is no first indubitable principle upon which all our beliefs can be based, and that even if there was we could not make any use of it, because as long as we distrust our cognitive faculties we cannot make any certain deductions from the first principle. (12.3)

    3.     What is consequent scepticism?

A doubt of the truth of our previous opinions and the reliability of our cognitive faculties that arises from a profound inquiry into the basis of those opinions and the manner of operation of those faculties. (12.5)

    4.     What are the “trite topics” employed by the sceptics in all ages, and what is Hume’s estimate of the value of these topics?

The trite topics are the classic perceptual relativity arguments, such as the ones found in the “modes” of the Ancient sceptics.  Hume thinks these topics are only adequate to prove that the evidence of the senses must be relativized to circumstances and subjected to the corroboration of the other senses and of reason. (12.6)

    5.     What do we take external objects to be when we follow the blind and powerful instinct of our nature?

The images presented by our senses. (12.8)

    6.     What does the slightest philosophy teach us that external objects are?

Something distinct from the images or perceptions presented to us by our senses that can remain the same even when those impressions change. (12.9)

    7.     What could cause the perceptions of the mind besides external objects?

The mind itself (as it in fact does when dreaming), or some other spirit, like a God or demon, or some alien entity that we can’t even conceive of. (12.11)

    8.     Why can experience not tell us what causes our perceptions?

Because all we ever experience is the perceptions themselves, not the objects that cause them. (And, of course, if you have never experienced the cause of an effect in the past, then none of your current experiences of the effect can lead you to draw any inferences about what it is.  The identity of causes can never be deduced ahead of time, simply by inspecting their effects.)  (12.12)

    9.     What did Hume mean by calling the sensible qualities secondary?

That they exist only in the mind as its perceptions, and not in bodies. (12.15)

10.     Why must the primary qualities exist only in the mind?

Because we cannot conceive how there could be such a thing as shape or size without colour or solidity, and we cannot conceive solidity without conceiving of either some tangible quality or moving colour patches being turned back by another colour patch.  Thus, the notions of pure extension and pure solidity apart from all sensible qualities make no sense.  Insofar as we understand anything by these notions, therefore, they refer to something that can only exist where the sensible qualities exist, namely, in the mind. (12.15)

11.     What is the chief objection against all abstract reasoning?

The fact that the ideas of infinitely divisible space and time are fundamentally incoherent and generate paradoxes. (12.18)

12.     What are the popular objections to our knowledge of matters of fact and why are they weak?

The popular objections appeal to the existence of widespread disagreement about matters of fact, be they between different times and cultures, different people, the same person at different time, or different faculties of the same person at the same time.  They also appeal to the fact that we have often made mistakes in our judgments of matters of fact.  Hume supposed that our instinctive tendency to draw inferences about matters of fact in light of our past experience is too strong to be blocked by these sorts of considerations.  While a recognition of conflict and past error over matters of fact might give us an academic appreciation of the weakness of our powers of inference, we will be instinctively impelled to go ahead and use those powers anyway.  Hume may also have wanted to suggest that as long as our natural instincts induce us to make judgments about matters of fact that turn out to be most often correct (that is, that allow us to subsist, and get by in life), the relatively fewer number of cases where we have been misled will not be able to induce a natural distrust of our instinctive inferences.  As long as our inferences from cause and effect have generally proven to be reliable in the past, they will have the weight of the evidence of experience on their side and the contrary cases that the popular sceptical objections draw to our attention will not be numerous enough to “destroy that evidence.” (12.21)

13.     What do the philosophical objections to our knowledge of matters of fact assert?

That any conclusions we draw about matters of fact that lie beyond the reach of our senses and memory are based on nothing more than the observation of a constant conjunction in the past combined with a natural instinct to transfer that experience to the future, and that this instinct could possibly mislead us since there is no good reason why the future should resemble the past. (12.23)

14.     What is the most that a Pyrrhonian can manage to do with his or her arguments?

Induce a temporary surprise, confusion, and dismay by showing us that there is no foundation for beliefs we nonetheless must have and are naturally compelled to have (12.23), but also give us a more lasting sense of the weakness of the human knowing powers (12.24), and a disposition to restrict our knowledge claims to matters closely analogous to those we have experienced in the past (12.25).

15.     What are the two main useful results that might follow when excessive scepticism is in some measure corrected by common sense and reflection?

They will lead dogmatic reasoners to be more diffident of their conclusions and more tolerant of the views of others (12.24), and lead us all to confine our investigations to topics that better fall within our capacities and refrain from distant and high inquiries (12.25)