15

Descartes, Meditations VIb

(AT VII 80-90)

 

EUCARISTIA_-_Raffaello2

 

Over the second half of Meditations VI, Descartes looked in more detail at what he could know about material things.  His investigation was guided by the principle that “because of the very fact that God is not a deceiver … it is impossible for there to be any falsity in my opinions which I cannot correct with another faculty God has given me” (AT VII 80).  He was particularly concerned with the opinion that material things resemble the ideas we receive of them through our senses, right down to their weight, heat, colour, and taste, and with a related opinion that spaces in which there is nothing that can be sensed are empty.  Together these opinions entail that space is distinct from body, because there can be spaces where there is no body, and because bodies have other qualities than just those that have to do with being spatially extended.  Descartes wanted, on the contrary, to identify space and body with one another, and hold that wherever there is space there is body and that body is nothing more than cut-up bits of space.  To support his position, he offered an account of God’s purpose in giving us sensations, an account that takes off from an understanding of our nature as thinking beings, who have been joined to a particular body in such a way that their continued union can be facilitated or impaired by surrounding bodies.  (Descartes liked to speak of things that facilitate or impair the mind body union rather than things that might preserve us or kill us because he considered the mind to be immortal.)  This investigation culminated in the statement that “sense perceptions are, strictly speaking, given to me by nature merely to indicate to my mind which things are agreeable or disagreeable to that combination of which it is a part,” and not for recognizing “the essence of bodies placed outside of me.” (AT VII 83)  This conclusion gave rise to a further problem arising from the fact that there are cases in which our sensations cause us to impair or even destroy the mind body union.  (The disease of dropsy, which is characterized by feelings of thirst that worsen the condition if satisfied, is an example.)  Descartes attempted to resolve this problem over the closing pages of the mediation.

This set of notes culminates with a discussion of two problems raised by the position Descartes took in Meditations VI: the problem of mind/body interaction, and a problem his identification of body with space posed for accepted Catholic doctrine on the sacrament of the Eucharist.

 

QUESTIONS ON THE READING

   1.    Why is it that even though Descartes thought he could demonstrate that corporeal things must exist, he still did not think that those things exist exactly as we grasp them by sense?  What must be true of them?

   2.    What things did Descartes think are taught to us by nature and what by a habit of making reckless judgments?

   3.    What is the proper purpose for which sensations were given to the mind?

   4.    Did Descartes think that all the motions of our bodies are mechanically caused?

   5.    What is necessary if the mind is to be affected by the body?

   6.    Does the brain feel pain?

   7.    Why is it in fact better that our senses should occasionally deceive us about what is good or bad for us?

   8.    What needs to be done in order to be sure that our senses are not deceiving us?

   9.    In what does the difference between dreaming and waking experience consist?

 

NOTES ON THE READING

The proof of the existence of material things given over the first half of Meditations VI establishes that my sensory ideas must be caused by something that is spatially extended.  This is because spatial extension is the one feature that is objectively present in my sensory ideas that I know to be a real, positive thing rather than a materially false idea of nothing.  And God would be a deceiver if the cause of my sensory ideas did not actually contain everything that is objectively present in those ideas.

But while Descartes’s proof establishes that my sensory ideas must be caused by a spatially extended thing or things, it does not justify my earlier opinion that the causes of my sensory ideas must be spatially extended in exactly the way the objects depicted in those ideas are spatially extended.  Because God is not a deceiver, there can be no incorrigible falsity in my opinions.  But in this case, subsequent sensory experience and reasoning tell me that objects are not always extended in exactly the way they are depicted as being extended in my initial sensory experiences.  Square towers seen from a distance look round, and many distant objects appear to be much smaller than they actually are.  There are many other such examples.

This having been said, Descartes was unwilling to retreat to the view that all we can ever know for sure is just that our bodies are extended in some way or other.  Careful use of our senses and our reasoning ability to correct one another’s information and one another’s speculations ought to bring us some way towards the truth, and there are certain strong natural impulses we have on these matters that cannot be denied. For Descartes’s larger purposes (notably, establishing that we can know that body is nothing more than just spatial extension and is not heavy or solid or hot or coloured, etc.), I can be assured of at least these general things: that there are many different bodies in existence, that one of these bodies is special to me, and that the various other bodies can affect this one special body, some for better, others for worse.

Though, as a thinking being, I am “really distinct” from anything extended, it appears to have been the will of God that I be unified or bound up with a particular extended thing, my body.  As a thinking thing I am also likely “naturally immortal,” simply because I am not extended in space and so cannot be broken to pieces.  But this natural immortality notwithstanding, God appears to have willed that I do everything in my power to preserve my union with the special body I call my own.

To this end, God has not joined me to my body in the way a sailor is joined to a ship.  A good sailor understands the state a ship is in, and knows when it has fallen into disrepair and what must be done to sail it out of danger.  But I do not understand these things about my body.  Instead, I feel them.  When the body is in disrepair, I feel pain and a need to move it in ways that will remove the pain even though I may not understand why those motions are effective.  Likewise, when the body is in danger or in need of things like food or drink I feel sensations like fear, hunger, or thirst that drive me to do what is needed to keep the body in the state required to “preserve the mind/body union,” that is, to prevent what we call “death,” which is really just the separation of the mind from the body.  I don’t understand the mechanism of the body or how other objects interact with it to benefit it or harm it.  I don’t know what makes different foods nutritious or noxious.  I just feel needs that prompt me to eat or drink, and I experience smells and tastes and feelings of heat and cold that prompt me to eat or drink this rather than that, or do other things that are in fact necessary for my health, that is, my continued union with my body.  Though these feelings do not give me the sort of understanding of the way my body interacts with its surroundings that a sailor has of the way a ship works, they are particularly effective means to induce me to do what is in fact necessary to preserve the mind/body union.  The sailor’s understanding takes time to acquire and even when acquired it may not motivate the sailor with any strong concern, as the sailor can simply decide to sail the ship to pieces and then transfer to another.  But I needed to be motivated to act in the right way to preserve the mind/body union while still a child who lacked the reasoning ability, or a young adult, who had it, but lacked the instruction.  And I could not be allowed to let the body fall into disrepair the way a sailor can, who sees the state of disrepair the ship is in but does not feel any pain over that fact.

Thinking along these lines led Descartes to conclude that the reason all of my sensations were given to me was to assist me in preserving the mind-body union.  Hunger, thirst, and other appetites teach me what is necessary for me to do to maintain the body.  Pleasure and pain teach me what objects to pursue and avoid.  Smells and tastes teach me what objects are nutritious or noxious.  Colour and sound to enable me to tell bodies apart from one another when observed from a safe distance.  And so on.  The purpose of these sensations is not to reveal the essence or the properties or the internal constitution of objects to me, but simply to assist me in determining which are beneficial and which harmful to the mind body union.

Having drawn this conclusion, Descartes was in a position to reject the natural impulse to consider bodies to be coloured or hot or cold or possessed of other sensible qualities like those we find in our sensory ideas.  This impulse is a “juvenile preconception,” formed in our youth and never subsequently considered.  When we consider what God’s purpose was in giving us sensations, we realize that it was never to reveal the nature of external objects to us.  The proper tool for investigating that nature is just the understanding, and it tells us that we can only be assured that bodies are extended.  Our impulse to think they are more than cut up bits of space was given to us for an entirely different purpose.

The prejudice that spaces that do not contain anything that affects our senses must be empty must likewise be abandoned.  All we can justly conclude is that such spaces do not contain anything that it is important for us to know about for purposes of survival.  What we have since learned about germs and disease, or environmental toxins and radioactivity shows that Descartes was mistaken about this, but it was a plausible enough thing to think for the time.  It is, moreover, entirely consistent with the view that these spaces are not truly empty but contain things too small to see.  That these things should happen to be dangerous to the mind/body union is something Descartes himself noted when he mentioned poisoned food (poisoning was a favourite method of assassination at the time).  God cannot be expected to have made us sensitive to everything in the environment that might be dangerous to the mind/body union, he observed.  He is not obliged to make us omniscient.  It is enough that we understand that his purposes in giving us those sensations we have was to enable us to do something to preserve that union, rather than to give us insight into the true nature of things.

 

Sensory illusion.  There is a more serious problem with this account of the purpose of sensory experience.  It is one thing for our senses to fail to inform us about things that are dangerous to the mind/body union.  It is quite another for them to misinform us, and induce us to do things that might be bad for us.  Some of this might be due to willful perversity on our part, as when we persist in consuming in alcohol or tobacco or other substances that appear noxious to us on first encounter, or when we spice and season foods to make them artificially palatable so that we over-indulge.   But there are other cases where we cannot so easily be blamed.  Descartes instanced the sensation of thirst felt by a person with dropsy — a sensation that, if satisfied, would actually worsen the body’s condition.  Should we treat these sorts of experiences the way we treat experiences of square towers that look round from a distance — as evidence that what our senses tell us about what is good or bad for the mind/body union is not implicitly to be trusted?  This is hardly tenable.  There is a particular urgency to our obtaining knowledge of the state of our own bodies.  We cannot afford to indulge in doubts about, say, whether we really need to move away from the fire or not. But given the particular urgency of this matter, it is particularly disturbing that God should not have given us reliable sensations of pleasure and pain.  How is this fact to be reconciled with his goodness?

Descartes’s reply to this problem what that this is a case where God really could not have made things any better than he did.  This sort of design flaw is one that is inevitable when making a being that is a union of a mind with a body.  To explain why, Descartes developed a theory of the physiology of sensation, and an account of the mechanics of the mind/body union.

The body, Descartes observed, is an extended thing, and as such is divisible into a number of parts, indeed into infinitely many parts. But the mind is not divisible into parts.  It might carry out different activities, such as willing or understanding or sensing, but it is not divisible into a willing part that is set outside of the understanding part, or a sensing part that is set outside of the other two (the sensing function might be a redundant one that the mind need not perform, but it is not an external part that could be cut off with a scalpel).  Moreover, experiments with amputations would seem to indicate that the mind is not in communication with each and every one of the body’s parts (I find myself to be as completely and wholly contained in what is left of my body after the loss of a limb or an eye as I was previously in the whole; none of my mind seems to have been cut off with the amputated part).  Insofar as it is united with the body, it is joined to it just at a small part, likely in the brain.

If we accept that the mind communicates with the body in the brain, and that external objects communicate with it at the surface of the sense organs, something has to happen to bring the effect from the sense organ to the mind.  Consistent with his belief that all we can be sure bodies have is extension and motion, Descartes supposed that what happens in sensation is that certain bodies either emit or reflect particles or themselves fly through the air and hit our sense organs.  Depending on the shape and motion and size of these impacting bodies, the sense organs are impressed, like wax, or made to vibrate, like drum skins.  Behind the sense organ Descartes supposed there to be a number of “tubes” or “strings” — the nerves.  (If the nerves are tubes, then they are filled with a very fine, vaporous fluid or gas called the animal spirits.)  The effect of impression or vibration of the sense organ is to “pull” on the nerve cord, or change the motions of the animal spirits flowing through the nerves.  These effects are propagated along the nerves and into the brain, where a physical organ called the corporeal imagination is impressed.  Impressions on the corporeal imagination in turn, through more nerves, propagate impressions to the part of the brain that communicates DescartesTouchwith the soul. At this point the soul is inspired to produce the idea that God ordained should correspond to that particular motion.

Even if this story is not correct in all of its details, it makes a general point that Descartes took to be beyond doubt: given that our bodies are extended and our minds capable of communicating with them only at a point, it is inevitable that sensation be the product of transmitting a signal from receptors on the body’s surface in to the locus of its communication with the mind.   But this means that, equally inevitably, there will be some chance that the process of sensation will be interfered with, due to agents acting within the body to interrupt, alter, or even generate a signal in the absence of its usual cause.  This is a feature of the design that follows necessarily from the fact that an unextended mind has been joined to an extended body, and even God could not do anything to rectify it.

In the case of vision and hearing this problem is magnified, because these senses inform us of things that exist at a distance from us, and there is a further chain of causes (e.g., reflected and refracted light rays, echoes) intervening between the object and the sense organ, creating yet more avenues for interference or distortion.

God has designed us in such a way that certain kinds of signal, coming to the locus of the soul from the receptors on the outer surface of the body, arouse certain kinds of ideas of sensation in the mind.  And, being all good, God will have made us so that the ideas that are aroused by a signal are the ones that, in the great preponderance of cases, we ought to get: the ones that will correctly represent whether the object is good or bad for us and that will correctly inform us about where those objects are and how they are shaped and moving.  That is:

 

  the ideas we get of the shape, size, position, order, and motion of objects are ideas that represent the actual shape, size, position, order, and motion of the objects normally causing the signal;

  the ideas we get of the sensible qualities contained within a particular figure at least correspond to some smaller structure of parts within the figure of the objects normally causing the signal so that same corpuscular structures always bring about same ideas

  our ideas of pleasure and pain are caused by truly beneficial or harmful corpuscular structures in the objects normally causing the signal;

  our sensations of bodily states like hunger, thirst, fatigue, and cramping, are linked to volitions to move our bodies in ways that are truly beneficial to the union.

 

It is just that, sometimes, these signals can be interfered with, either by very small, undetectable parts entering into the bodies that normally cause a sensation, or by some agent interfering with the transmission of the signal en route.  God can do nothing to prevent this, and it is rather a mark of his goodness that we have been designed so as to get the correct ideas in normal circumstances.

This means that, in normal circumstances, we can trust our senses to inform us accurately about the disposition of objects in space around our bodies, about at least their larger-scale shapes, sizes, positions, orders and motions, about which ones are different in ways that do not depend on their gross size or shape, and about whether they are good or bad for us.  Moreover, when mistakes are made they will typically be the result of some specific agent interfering with the connection between one of the sense organs and the brain.  It is unlikely that all five senses, distributed throughout the body as they are, would simultaneously be attacked at once.  Consequently, we have a ready means at our disposal to correct almost all sensory errors.  We need merely be careful to check the reports given by one sense against those given by the others and assent only to those reports that all the senses agree on giving.

At the close of Meditations VI Descartes applied this claim to resolve the doubts raised by the dreaming argument.  He claimed that as long as we bring all our faculties, particularly our memory, to bear before making a judgment, we will discover that dreams contain tell-tale discontinuities.  When the dreaming sequence starts, a whole scene just pops into existence without our being able to tell where it came from or how we got to be there observing it.  Moreover, in dreams events frequently occur that are in violation of established laws of nature. In waking life, in contrast, there is continuity to our experience and a rigorous obedience of events to natural laws.  Therefore, we need only consider whether our experiences are coherent and regular in order to discriminate waking from dreaming experiences.

Though it is not explicit, this argument most likely depends on the same appeal to the goodness of God in not allowing us to be deceived that all of the other doctrines of the second half of Meditations VI presuppose.  It is logically possible that we could have coherent dreams. It is also logically possible that we might dream that we remember a coherent past to our current dream.  Descartes seems to have rejected these possibilities on the ground that God would not have made our memories defective in any irremediable or undetectable way, and would not have allowed us to have dreams that are so coherent as to be more than temporarily undetectable.

All this having been said, the concluding sentence of the Meditations remains worth quoting and considering.

 

But because the need to get things done does not always permit us the leisure for such a careful inquiry, we must confess that the life of man is apt to commit errors regarding particular things, and we must acknowledge the infirmity of our nature.

 

In the end, absolute certainty in all things is neither possible nor necessary.  The demands of daily life are often such as to prohibit taking the time for a careful examination of whether all the senses, memory, and the understanding agree on some point.  As a consequence we will continue to get things wrong.  The Meditations has not provided us with a remedy for all error.  But, in Descartes’s estimation, it has at least provided us with certainty about some very basic and foundational truths, and so a secure foundation on which to build the rest of our knowledge, fallible though that superstructure might turn out to be.

 

CARTESIAN DUALISM

One of the most serious challenges faced by the Cartesian philosophy concerns the nature of the mind/body union and the manner in which mind and body might interact with one another.  Critics have charged that it is impossible to understand how the mind is able to move the body or the body able to cause the mind to experience sensations, and that it is impossible to understand how two such radically distinct substances could be welded together to form the “substantial union” Descartes spoke of in Meditations VI.

DescartesVision1

This problem becomes particularly acute in connection with Descartes’s attempt to resolve the problem of sensory error.  In that attempt, he maintained that since the mind is unextended and the body extended, there must be just one place within the body where the two communicate. Earlier, this claim was defended by appeal to experiments with amputations.  But these experiments only provide partial confirmation of Descartes’s position.  Were I to have a stroke, or were a part of my brain to be amputated, I would sense that I had lost a part of my mental capacities.  This suggests that the mind may be connected with the body at more than just a point, and that severing off parts of the brain may be tantamount to severing off parts of the mind.

Hobbes’s materialism took this consequence to its logical conclusion: simply deny that there is any such thing as mind and attempt to account for all the characteristic mental functions by reducing them to operations of the brain.  Berkeley’s immaterialism offered another solution to the mind/body problem: simply deny that there is any such thing as matter and maintain that nothing exists but minds that receive the same sorts of ideas they would receive if there were material things.

Those who have been unwilling to accept either of these radical solutions are called dualists, because they follow Descartes in holding that mind and body are two distinct kinds of thing, neither of which is reducible to the other, and they have inherited Descartes’s problem of accounting for how the thing in us that senses, thinks, and wills could interact with the body.  Among the solutions to this problem that dualists have come up with are Leibniz’s pre-established harmony, Spinoza’s double aspect theory, and Malebranche’s occasionalism.  According to the theory of pre-established harmony there are both material and spiritual things, but neither interacts in any way with the other; rather, like two clocks that independently tell the same time, each evolves over time in accord with its own internal principles, but does so in such a way that changes in the one just happen to be completely in accord with changes in the other.  According to the double aspect theory, there is really only one substance, but this substance appears to us in two different ways depending on whether it is considered through the senses or through the intellect; therefore, mind does not interact with body; there is just one thing that changes over time and that appears in one way as a body in motion (when viewed using the senses) and in another way as a mind with ideas (when viewed using the intellect).  According to the theory of occasionalism, God is constantly inspecting minds and bodies, and on those occasions where particular motions occur in the sensory parts of the brain, God causes the mind to experience corresponding ideas of sense, whereas on those occasions where particular volitions occur in the mind, God moves the body in corresponding ways.

Descartes’s own position on this problem is difficult to make out. While some of his remarks might be taken to suggest a commitment to occasionalism, his claims that when God made us he mixed two distinct substances to form a substantial union, and that the mind is naturally so constituted as to receive certain sensations as a consequence of affection of the corporeal imagination, suggest that he may have held that there is some sort of real causal interaction between the mind and the body.  But since the interaction cannot take place at many points without treating the mind as coextensive with the brain and reverting to Hobbist materialism, the one-point interaction theory appears to have been Descartes’s only remaining option.  The precise nature of his position continues to be a matter of dispute among commentators.

 

SUBSTANCE, REAL QUALITIES, AND THE EUCHARIST

 

One of the most serious difficulties with Descartes position in the Catholic France of his own day concerned the threat his philosophy was taken to pose for the doctrine of transubstantiation and the theology of the Eucharist.  Unlike the more internal, enthusiastic and iconoclastic forms of Reformed Protestantism dominant in England and Holland, Catholicism tended to place emphasis on a more external, ritualistic form of worship, involving beliefs and ceremonies that the Protestants denounced as absurd and superstitious.  One such element was the ceremony of the Eucharist, where, in imitation of events reported to have taken place at the “Last Supper” between Jesus Christ and his disciples, a piece of bread and a goblet of wine are supposed to be literally (not just figuratively or metaphorically) turned into the body and blood of Christ, despite continuing to look to all appearances like bread and wine.  The Protestants had maintained that Christ should be understood to be only spiritually present in the bread and wine, but the Catholics had denounced this as a patent heresy.  Christ had reportedly said “This is my body … this is my blood.”  The Catholics took this to be meant literally.  And they insisted that ordained Priests acquired the power to re-enact this miracle during their religious ceremonies.  Of course, the bread and wine continue to look and taste like bread and wine, even after the miracle has been performed (though there were, of course, occasional reports of more literal sightings).  But, according to the Catholics, they have really been transformed or “transubstantiated,” notwithstanding the appearances.  This belief was underwritten by the Aristotelian notions of substance and real quality.  At the moment when the priest “consecrates” the bread and wine, it was thought that the essence or substantial form of the host changes from that of bread to that of the body and blood of Christ.  However, all the merely “accidental” qualities that were previously evident in the bread and wine continue to be there (which is why it still looks, feels, tastes, and smells the same).  However, these qualities subsist outside of any substance (the substance of Christ’s body and blood was not supposed to take on these accidental qualities but to exist apart from them).  Crucial to this explanation of the miracle is the notion that sensible qualities like colour, smell, and taste, are real qualities that exist outside of us and that can even exist apart from the substances in which they normally inhere.  Even more interestingly, this was taken to extend, not just to the sensible qualities of smell, taste, and colour, but also to the extension, shape, size, motion and solidity of the bread and wine.  The substance of Christ’s body was supposed to exist distinctly from the particular extension of the bread and wine, a detail that allowed the Catholics to maintain that the whole of the body of Christ could be present in even very oddly shaped small fragments of the bread and wine.

Insofar as the Cartesian philosophy is unfriendly to the existence of real qualities, it is unclear that it can countenance the miracle of the Eucharist.  This is a problem that was raised by Arnauld in his fourth set of objections to the Meditations.  Arnauld wrote:

 

But what I see as likely to give the greatest offence to theologians is that according to the author’s doctrines it seems that the Church’s teaching concerning the sacred mysteries of the Eucharist cannot remain completely intact.

We believe on faith that the substance of the bread is taken away from the bread of the Eucharist and only the accidents remain. These are extension, shape, colour, smell, taste and other qualities perceived by the senses.

But the author thinks there are no sensible qualities, but merely various motions in the bodies that surround us which enable us to perceive the various impressions which we subsequently call ‘colour,’ ‘taste’ and ‘smell.’ Hence only shape, extension and mobility remain. Yet the author denies that these powers are intelligible apart from some substance for them to inhere in, and hence he holds that they cannot exist without such a substance. …

Further, he recognizes no distinction between the states of a substance and the substance itself except for a formal one; yet this kind of distinction seems insufficient to allow for the states to be separated from the substance even by God.

 

Questioning the mystery of the Eucharist was something that Descartes wanted, at all costs to avoid.  Two paths were open to him.  One was circumspection of the sort we have seen him recommend to Regius, cited at the end of Chapter 7.  Taking this path would mean refraining from denying outright that sensible qualities are real things.  It would mean instead maintaining that while we have excellent reasons for concluding that external objects must be extended and so must possess the modifications of which extension is capable, we do not have the same reasons to think that they must have any other sort of qualities.  They might possibly have further qualities, though we have no need to suppose any other such qualities when giving scientific explanations.  If we accept that bodies have further qualities, it is not because we very clearly and distinctly perceive that they must but only because this is a truth that has been revealed to us (by the Biblical account of the last supper and the accepted theology regarding the Eucharist in particular).  We might think that Descartes had good reasons to take this path, because the arguments of Meditations VI are simply not strong enough to give us reason to deny the existence of real sensible qualities.  Those arguments go so far as to assure us that bodies must have the primary qualities of extension and motion, but they do not rule out the possibility that bodies might turn out to have other qualities as well.  At best, they tell us that we are in no position to know this without the assistance of revelation.

But in the end, this was a path that Descartes could not take.  Allowing for even the possibility of the existence of real qualities would undermine his physics, which was invested in the notion that bodies can have no other qualities than those that arise from extension.  So Descartes took a different route.  He attempted to reconcile his philosophy with the doctrine of transubstantiation.  His reply to Arnauld invoked a distinction between the “superficies” or outer surface of a body (including all its pores, if it has them, or the outlines of all of its parts, if it has independently movable parts) and the material contained within this superficies.  The latter could change while the former remains the same he maintained.  But were this to happen, the body would continue to affect our sense organs in the same way, and so bring about the same sensations in us, even though it is constituted of material of an entirely different kind (that is, even though its ultimate parts are differently shaped and moving).  This, in his estimation, constitutes a far more intelligible explanation of the primary doctrine, that of transubstantiation, than that offered by the Scholastics with their commitment to real qualities.  It preserves the essential tenet that the substance changes while the way it acts on us remains the same, at the same time avoiding the Protestant heresies on this topic.

This did not go all the way to resolve the problem, however, and it was not intrinsically very satisfying.  It did not account for how an extended substance could be separated from its modes of size, shape, and motion, which was also a part of the doctrine, and it raised questions about how far the substance could have been really transformed if it continued to occupy the same superficies, given what Descartes had to say about how extended substances are distinguished from one another.  When pressed on these issues, Descartes became very reticent to go into detail, and turned to the claim that it is union with a mind that really makes a human substance the kind of thing it is.  The same would have to hold of the substance of Christ insofar as it shares any physical nature.  However, this was all too close to the Protestant view that Christ is merely “spiritually” present in the sacrament  for comfort, and Descartes knew it because he asked those to whom he had revealed these speculations to not reveal his identity.  Mesland, a Jesuit who corresponded with Descartes about these topics and who may have made some moves in the direction of getting Descartes’s philosophy endorsed by the Jesuits, was sent off to the missions in Canada where he died a few years later.  Descartes himself lived most of his life in Protestant Holland, even then moving frequently and doing his best to keep his whereabouts a secret from all but trusted friends.

 

ESSAY QUESTIONS AND RESEARCH PROJECTS

   1.    Over the course of the Meditations, and particularly over the second half of Meditations VI, Descartes frequently invoked the term, “nature,” and discriminated a number of different kinds of “nature” and senses in which he wanted the term,”nature” to be understood.  “Nature taken generally” is defined at AT VII 80, but there is another definition of “nature taken more narrowly” at AT VII 82.  Descartes outlined correspondingly different accounts of what is “taught by nature” in each of these senses and what is taught to us by “a certain habit of making reckless judgments.”  At AT VII he also contrasted what has been “taught by nature” with what is known in the “light of nature.” And over AT VII 84-85 “nature” is used again in a “latter” and a “former” sense that do not bear any obvious relation to either the “general” or the “narrow” definitions of “nature.”  Taking all of these passages into account, formulate a general account of Descartes’s position on “nature” in all of its senses.  Determine whether he managed to clearly separate the different senses of the term.

   2.    Did Descartes have any principled way of distinguishing between what is “taught to us by nature” and what is taught to us by “a certain habit of making reckless judgments” or is this distinction irredeemably confused and ambiguous?

   3.    Undertake a study of Descartes’s correspondence and that of his contemporaries in order to determine exactly what problems he got into over the issue of the Eucharist and why.

   4.    One of Descartes’s most astute critics was Princess Elizabeth of Bohemia, who pressed him on the issue of the nature of the relation between the soul and the body.  Descartes’s The passions of the soul is in part an attempt to address her concerns.  Do a study of Descartes’s correspondence with Elizabeth and draw up an account of what Elizabeth’s main concerns were and how Descartes attempted to address them.  Assess the adequacy of Descartes’s responses to Elizabeth.

   5.    Undertake a this same project with reference to Descartes replies to the author of the fifth set of the objections to the Meditations, Pierre Gassendi.

   6.    Did Descartes come up with an adequate response to the dreaming argument?