8

Descartes, Principles I.1-23

the demonstrations are so certain that even if our experience seemed to show the opposite, we should still be obliged to have more faith in our reason than in our senses.

– Descartes, Principles of philosophy, Part II, Article 52

 

Description: DescartesPrinciplesIn the autobiographical remarks that occur in the first section of his Discourse on Method, Descartes recounted how he had come to be disappointed with book-learning and how, as soon as he was old enough to emerge from the control of his teachers, he had abandoned the study of letters and resolved instead to travel and gain what knowledge he could from “the book of the world,” that is from experience.  He also remarked that there is much more truth to be found in reasoning about practical matters than in highly theoretical speculations.  This is because, if one makes a mistake in practical matters, one soon discovers one’s error, because practical matters have immediate consequences that are good or bad for you.  Mistakes in theoretical speculations, in contrast, do not come to be so readily apparent (AT VI 9-10).  But Descartes thought that this is far from meaning that we should prefer experience and induction from experience to purely intellectual theorizing.  On the contrary, he remarked that the main thing his travels and experiences had taught him was that one ought not to place any firm trust in what one has learned only by example and experience.  Ironically, experience itself teaches us not to rely too much on experience, by revealing the diversity of practices and opinions among different nations.  Apparently, even the fact that one’s actions can have immediate good or bad consequences does not prevent people from adopting very different practices; and the fact that we all experience the same world does not prevent us from forming very different opinions about it.  The main thing Descartes’s experience of this diversity had done was free him from his own prejudices by showing him how many of the things he had previously taken to be certain were not accepted by others.  This had sensitized him to the great difference there is between what only seems certain because it is common and habitual and what actually is such that our minds simply cannot conceive an alternative.  Descartes concluded the first section of the Discourse by noting that his travels and experiences had prepared him for an entirely different study: they had prepared him to turn away from the world and look within himself.  What he hoped to find within himself was something more certain than anything he had learned from his teachers or his travels: absolutely indubitable first or starting principles that can be used as the foundation or the initial premises for deriving all the rest of our knowledge.

This quest for foundational principles is one of the characteristic features of Descartes’s philosophy.  Other philosophers have been willing to settle for less — for probability or for provisional suppositions that, while not certainly true, can be confirmed by sensory experience.  However, Descartes’s conception of the proper method for gaining knowledge left him with no choice but to make stronger demands.  The first rule of his method dictates that we start with axioms, and the third rule stipulates that all knowledge is to be obtained by deduction from these axioms.  The Descartes who had gone traveling to read the book of the world and learn lessons from experience had concluded that if mistakes are easier to discover in practical matters than in speculative ones, then the thing to do is not to turn to practical matters but to make sure that the foundations for your speculations are absolutely firm — so firm that they could stand even in the face of contrary sensory experience.  It bears noting in this context that Descartes was confident of the truth of the mechanist natural philosophy, which postulates that the real world looks very different from the coloured, scented, warm and cool bodies we experience through our senses.  He therefore expected that when he proceeded in accord with his method, his deductions from axioms would establish the existence of things that are very different from what we see around us.  But for Descartes, the fact that deductions from our theories might come into conflict with everyday experience or with common sense is not by itself a reason to think that the theories are wrong.  He did not pretend to verify his principles after the fact, by reference to their consequences.  Instead, he sought to ground them in absolutely certain first principles.

Descartes’s first order of business was to find such principles.

 

QUESTIONS ON THE READING

   1.    Why should we think that we are the victims of prejudices or “preconceived opinions” that have kept us from knowledge of the truth?

   2.    What is the “scale” of the doubt that Descartes proposed in Principles I.1?  What things does he propose to call into doubt and what things would he consider to be above doubt?

   3.    What is called into doubt by the fact that our senses sometimes deceive us and by the fact that there is no certain way of distinguishing being awake from dreaming?

   4.    Should we doubt principles that are revealed to us by reasoning?  If so, why?  If not, why not?

   5.    What are the limits of human freedom?

   6.    What makes my existence certain (beyond all possibility of doubt)?

   7.    What am I certain of when I claim to be certain of my own existence?  What else, besides myself, am I certain of insofar as I have this certainty of my own existence?

   8.    What is “known by the natural light?”

   9.    What determines that there must be some substance in existence?

10.    What makes our knowledge of a substance “clear”

11.    Why do we find more attributes in our minds than in anything else?

12.    Where does the power of sense perception reside?

13.    What makes it of paramount importance for us to determine what ultimately caused us to exist?

14.    Under what conditions is it possible to doubt the results of demonstrations?

15.    What is contained in the idea that the mind finds in itself of God that guarantees that the object of this idea must necessarily and eternally exist?

16.    Why must we conclude that the supreme being does exist?

17.    In what way are ideas different and in what way are they all alike?

18.    What is required to give someone the idea of an intricate object?  What assures us that this must be so?

19.    How can we have an idea of supreme perfections if we are ourselves imperfect?

20.    Why must the whole world be continually recreated from one moment to the next?

 

NOTES ON THE READING

Principles I.1-3.  The method of doubt.  Principles I.1 opens by proposing that we reject everything we have up to now supposed to be true and set about rebuilding the edifice of our knowledge on new foundations.  To justify this proposal, Descartes noted that we all began life as infants with very rudimentary cognitive abilities.  Probably, our sense organs worked as perfectly at birth or shortly after as they do now (if not better).  But our minds were so underdeveloped and the range of our experiences so narrow that we were in no position to make correct judgments about what we were experiencing.  We nonetheless did so, having no other choice.  In the process we arrived at such incorrect (to Descartes’s mind) views as that the objects of our experience actually possess the qualities of colour and heat that they appear to have, that there are empty spaces, and that we are the bodies our senses reveal to us.  Growing up with them, these judgments became habitual, and gradually turned into prejudices, only confirmed by the customary opinions of those around us, who had grown up in similar circumstances.  They came to us to seem so natural and obvious as to be certainly true.  But as basic as such truths may seem, surely, we ought not to trust to such a haphazard way of arriving at them.  Even apart from traveling and discovering how different the practices and opinions of others are concerning other things that we take to be equally natural and evident, we ought to think that it is a mistake to trust to juvenile habits and conceits.  We ought to at least once look carefully within ourselves and consider what is really certain and evident, and what is only customary and habitual.  The best way to draw the distinction is to ask ourselves what is beyond all shadow of a doubt.  Whatever emerges as being beyond all shadow of a doubt could surely be no immature preconception, but would have to be a sound judgment.

Since most of what we know is based on sense experience or reason, Descartes first considered the reliability of what we have come to know on the basis of these two “principles.”  The results that he came up with were devastating.  Principles I.4-5 offer two powerful arguments for doubting what we have learned from sensory experience and what we have discovered by reasoning.  These arguments are commonly referred to as the dreaming argument and the deceiver argument.

 

Principles I.4.  The dreaming argument.  Prior to Descartes, philosophers wishing to question the reliability of sensory experience had commonly appealed to a set of arguments known as the sceptical “modes.”  Sceptics would employ the “modes” to show that one and the same object can appear differently to different animals, to different human beings, to different sense organs, to the same sense organ under different circumstances, and so on.  This would hopefully convince the listener that we have no direct knowledge of the nature of objects, but only of appearances, and that the appearances of one and the same object are so numerous and different that there is no way of telling what it is really like.

But Descartes had little use for the sceptical modes.  While he did note that our senses have from time to time presented objects as being different than we have reason to think they really are, he never put this point by claiming that they leave us with no way of deciding which appearance is the correct one.  He only took things so far as to say that our senses “sometimes” deceive us, suggesting that the deception is merely occasional and temporary, and that further sensory experience serves to uncover the error.  This still leaves us with some grounds to doubt sensory experience.  Since our senses have deceived us in the past we can wonder, on any given occasion, whether they might now be deceiving us and whether further experience will uncover some error.  But the progress of our experience leaves us with no reason to think that our senses might be systematically deceptive — that they might deceive us so consistently as never to bring up anything that would lead us to notice the deceit.

There is a different reason to think that our senses might be systematically deceptive: the possibility that we might be dreaming.

Descartes supposed that I have no way of definitively ruling out the possibility that I might now be asleep and dreaming.  The fact that my current experiences are rich, detailed, and vivid does not prove that they are not dreamed up since I have in the past had dreams that are rich, detailed and vivid.  Or, at the very least, I can well conceive it possible that I might have such a dream.  Similarly, the fact that I now seem to remember a continuous, coherent past, reaching back for many years and consisting of events that are uniformly ordinary and law-governed does not prove that I am not now dreaming.  For, even though many dreams are incoherent, this is not the case with all dreams.  Dreams can be as coherent as waking experiences and sometimes they can include dreamed up memories of a long, coherent history.  At least, it is possible that some dreams could be like this.  And as long as it is possible we cannot claim to know beyond a shadow of a doubt that dreams cannot be internally coherent and plausible.  Even the memory of having awakened is no sure indication I am not now dreaming, since I have had (or can well think it possible that I could have) dreams in which I dream that I wake up from a dream within the dream.  In general, it seems that any criterion anyone might care to use to try to distinguish dreams from waking experience could be undermined by the objection that we might just dream that the criterion has been met.

We might think that, despite these possibilities, we are pretty good at telling the difference between reality and dreams.  But for Descartes, being pretty good at determining the difference is not good enough.  We need to be absolutely certain.  As long as it is possible that we might be dreaming, we cannot claim to know for sure that we are not dreaming, even now.

But if I grant that there is no way of definitively ruling out the possibility that I am now dreaming, then doubts about the actual existence of everything revealed by sensory experience follow as a consequence.  Since things experienced in a dream are generally false, having no good way to determine that I am now awake means having no good way to determine that there is any actuality reflected in my current experience.  I cannot say that simply because I am seeing this page with these words printed on it, that therefore there must actually be a page with these words printed on it.  More radically, I cannot say that simply because I see myself surrounded by the walls of this room, in this building, in this city, in this country, that any such room, building, city, or country exists.  There may not even be a planet Earth or a universe like the one I now think I remember seeing when I last looked up at the stars at night.  Perhaps I am a being on a planet in another world who is merely dreaming all of these things and none of them actually exists, and in a moment I will wake up and discover my error.  Indeed, perhaps there is not a corporeal, extended world of any kind.  After all, setting aside the minority opinions of Hobbes and Epicurus, people have for centuries believed in the possibility of the existence of immaterial spirits like ghosts and angels.  These are things that exist without having physical bodies.  What is to say, therefore, that I might not be a sleeping angel, merely dreaming that it has a body?

Just as the dreaming argument should lead me to doubt whether I really have a body, and whether the surrounding world is at all like what I perceive it to be, so it should lead me to doubt whether there are any such things as the atoms and corpuscles imagined by the mechanical philosophers, or the forms and qualities imagined by the Aristotelians, or even the other people that we all imagine to inhabit our world.  Similarly, it should lead me to doubt whether any of the sciences that describe these things, such as physics, cosmology, and metaphysics are true.  After all, just as I may be an angel dreaming that it has a body, so I may be an angel in an aspatial spirit-world dreaming it is located somewhere in a world of bodies.  Indeed, I may be a single, solitary spirit, the sole thing in creation, dreaming that there is a world of extended bodies and other minds around it.

 

Principles I.5.  The deceiver argument.  What, then, about the sciences that don’t set out to describe anything that actually exists, but that deal with merely ideal things, sciences like arithmetic and geometry?  Even here there are reasons for doubt.  Descartes noted that we sometimes make mistakes in simple arithmetic even in waking life, as anyone who has tried to balance a check book knows only too well.  As with the case of occasional sensory deception, we might object that such mistakes are generally a product of haste and inattention, and can be revealed by proceeding more carefully and pausing to make frequent reviews of our calculations.  But once again there is a reason to think that our demonstrations and calculations might be not just occasionally but systematically deceptive.  It is possible that in his younger days Descartes may have attended the Loudun witchcraft trials and been impressed by the efforts of the defence attorneys to argue that if the Devil was as powerful as the Prosecution claimed he was, then he ought to be able to deceive the Court and the Judges into thinking that innocent people are witches.  Whether that is the case or not, the thought occurred to Descartes that, if a being powerful enough to have created the world exists, then that being ought to easily be able to ensure that every time I add two to three I come up with the same, wrong result.  A really powerful deceiver should be able to convince me that two plus three is six.  After all, I do occasionally make this mistake all on my own, so a deceiver should be able to make me make it systematically, and so foul up my entire knowledge of arithmetic.

This may be an extravagant possibility, but for Descartes, any reason for doubting a claim, however wild or extravagant, is a reason for setting that claim aside and going on to look for something else that might offer more certainty.  And so our reasoning in geometry and mathematics must be rejected as well as our sense experience of ourselves and the world around us.

 

Principles I.9, I.6, I.10.  Residual certainties.  Descartes went on to claim that there remain certain things we cannot bring ourselves to doubt, even in light of the fact that we might be dreaming or that a supremely powerful and resourceful being might be bending all its energies on attempting to deceive us. 

The possibility that we might be dreaming only puts us in a position to doubt the actual or external existence of the objects we encounter in dreams.  It does not put us in a position to doubt our experiences themselves.  There might be nothing in existence that corresponds to what we think we are experiencing, as is in fact the case in a dream.  The objects we think we see around us might not exist.  The objects that do exist might be nothing like those that we think we see around us so that nothing anywhere exists or ever has existed that resembles what we think we see around us.  We ourselves might not have the bodies we think we have or might perhaps be entirely disembodied.  Yet, all the same, even if we are dreaming, there are certain ideas or thoughts in us, and it seems impossible that we could be mistaken about that.  I cannot doubt that I am thinking of a red square without thinking of a red square.  Even a supremely powerful deceiver could not deceive me into thinking that I am thinking of a red square without giving me the thought of a red square and thereby making it true.

So it seems that all that the dreaming argument can lead us to doubt is that there are things currently located at places outside of us that are something like what we are currently experiencing.  But we cannot doubt the existence of our current experiences themselves, considered just as experiences.  At this level, even sensory experience is beyond doubt.  If I think I am sensing a printed page, at least the sensory experience of a printed page must exist in me, even if no printed page exists in the world outside of me.

There are also limitations on what the deceiver argument can lead us to doubt.  To see why, I first need to draw a distinction between things we know by reasoning and things we know by what I will call intuition.  Things we know by reasoning are the conclusions we draw from argument or demonstration.  But there are some things that we know (or think we know) without argument.  When we see something, we think we know it.  Of course, we have learned to doubt that what we see might actually exist outside of us.  But when we see something we at least cannot doubt that we are seeing something — that we are having some perceptual experience, even if it is only ideas in us.  We cannot doubt that we have thoughts in general.  Similarly, we cannot doubt that each thought is something and not nothing.  And when we have a particular thought, we cannot doubt that it is that thought rather than some other.  We cannot doubt that each thought is what it is and is not anything else.  Since each thought is what it is and cannot be otherwise, we cannot doubt that red is different from green.  Moreover, we cannot doubt that orange is more like red than it is like green.  Because each thought is what it is and is unlike any other, we can compare our different thoughts with one another and simply “see” that there are certain relations between these thoughts.  Many of these relations (for example, similarity and contrast, degrees in quality, differences of quantity) are what they are and cannot change without the ideas themselves changing.  This is what I mean by talking about an intuitive grasp or conviction.  An intuitive grasp or conviction is the kind of grasp or conviction we get when we contemplate our own ideas and just “see” that they stand in certain relations to one another.  We do not demonstrate these things by reasoning or argument.  They are rather the fundamental indemonstrable premises on which all reasoning is based.  Neither do we see these things with the eyes of our body in the light of the sun.  We rather see (or better “intuit”) them with the eyes of the mind in what Descartes liked to call “the light of nature” or “the natural light.”

Let me return from this digression about reasoning, perceiving, and intuiting to discuss the limitations on the deceiver argument.  We can imagine two ways in which a deceiver might deceive us.  The deceiver might make us perform demonstrations and calculations incorrectly every time we go to perform them, so that we never notice our mistake.  Alternatively, the deceiver might simply force us to believe certain absurd things, even apart from any proof.  Descartes was certainly concerned about the possibility of a deceiver who works in the first way, and leads us to systematically mistake the results of demonstration.  But what about the second?  Interestingly, we know for a fact that we are not compelled to believe just anything.  There are surprisingly many things we can bring ourselves to doubt, as this very course of argument we have been engaging in proves.  But there are also certain things that it seems it is simply not within our power to doubt.  These things are not the conclusions of reasoning or demonstration.  We have been able to convince ourselves to doubt those.  Neither are they the things we think we perceive to exist in the world outside us.  We have been able to convince ourselves to doubt those as well.  They are instead the intuitively obvious relations between ideas I spoke about earlier.

Descartes noted that, even if there is a deceiver, it is intuitively obvious that the deceiver has left us with a great deal of freedom to either accept or deny or doubt many things.  It is also intuitively obvious that there are certain things we cannot doubt — whether there is a deceiver or not.  If the deceiver is forcing us to believe these things even though they are really false or absurd, then our situation is hopeless, because we don’t even have it within our power to doubt them, even knowing that this is a possibility.  But could it even be possible for a deceiver to trick us about such things?  Or are the limits of our freedom in this regard are a reflection of what it would be impossible for even a supremely powerful deceiver to bring off?  If I intuitively grasp that red is not green, how could a deceiver deceive me about that fact other than by giving me ideas of red and green that are as a matter of fact different from one another, and thereby making it true after all?

These reflections led Descartes to conclude that if you really do intuitively grasp something — if what you know is the product of your immediately intuiting the presence of a certain relation between your own ideas — then there is no way even a deceiver could trick you about that.  This is the limitation on the deceiver argument.  It can lead us to doubt the conclusions of reasoning or demonstration.  But it cannot lead us to doubt what is immediately or intuitively evident as a “first truth” independently of all argument.

Of course this raises a question: how do we know for sure that we are really intuitively grasping something rather than simply falling back on some juvenile preconception?  But there is a ready answer.  If it really is intuitively grasped, it will be impossible for you to bring yourself to doubt it — impossible because, being an immediately perceived relation between ideas, you will see that there is no way that relation could fail to be there without the ideas being changed.  In other words, if it is intuitive, it simply cannot be thought of in any other way.  If you can even conceive of it being different, it is not intuitive, and you are not forced to believe it.  And if you can conceive of any means by which you might have gotten it wrong, it is not intuitive, and you are not forced to believe it.  We are not forced to believe even the results of simple demonstration, like 2+3=5, because we sometimes get those results wrong and because this means that wherever a chain of inference or argument is employed a deceiver could systematically trick us.  But even a deceiver could not make us think that a circle is not a square without giving us ideas of a circle and a square that look different from one another, and so making it so.

 

Principles I.7-8 and I.11-12.  Self-certainty and the distinction of mind from body.  For Descartes, our thoughts and the intuitively evident truths that are very clearly and distinctly revealed by comparing those thoughts with one another are not the only things that survive the dreaming and deceiver arguments.  More famously, and even prior to these other items, he also maintained that it is impossible for me to doubt my own existence.  As he put it at Principles I.7, “we cannot for all that suppose that we, who are having such thoughts, are nothing.  For it is a contradiction to suppose that what thinks does not, at the very time when it is thinking, exist.”

This further conclusion is less full blooded than it might appear because it begs a large question: what exactly am I supposing to exist when I suppose myself to exist?  As Descartes was at pains to go on to stress, all the doubts that arise from the possibility that I might be dreaming remain in force, which means that anything that I might be merely dreaming myself to be can be doubted.  I can’t doubt my thoughts, because even if I am dreaming I must be having those thoughts if I am dreaming them.  But I could be an amputee dreaming they still have the missing limb or, more radically, an angel dreaming it has a body.  So I can’t identify myself with my body.

Descartes fingered this result as a preliminary indication of one of the principal points he wanted to establish.  If I can doubt that I have a body while nonetheless being certain that I exist, this suggests that I might in fact be something quite distinct from that body that I have since youth identified myself with.  Though the dreaming argument should have convinced me that I cannot be certain of the existence of an external world or even of my own body, this is not the same thing as convincing me that I cannot be certain of my own existence.  After all, why should I think I need to have a body in order to exist?  Hobbes had wanted to maintain that the notion of an incorporeal substance makes no sense, but Descartes considered that the fact that I cannot doubt that my thoughts exist, while I can doubt that I have a body, is the best argument for a radical distinction between the two.  Mind and body are two entirely different things, the one in no way depending on the other.

The other grounds for doubt fare no better.  Might I just be dreaming that I exist?  Then I would have to be there to do the dreaming.  Might there be a deceiver who tries to trick me into believing that I exist when in fact I do not?  But how could the deceiver set out to deceive me unless I exist to be deceived?

So the belief in my own existence is certain because it resists all attempts to show that it is uncertain.

All the same, if I am not my body, what am I over and above just a collection of thoughts?

Descartes wanted to claim that I am something more.  I am a thing that has these thoughts, so that thoughts may be defined as “happenings” that occur “within” me (Principles I.9), or as attributes or qualities of some substance and I, considered as a substance, can be understood to be a characteristically or “essentially” thinking substance — a thing whose nature it is to think.  This is something of a leap.  It is moreover, a leap in a very odd direction for an early modern philosopher, concerned to reject an Aristotelian or Scholastic world view because it invokes the old, Aristotelian picture of the world as a collection of “substances” that possess “qualities.”  But Descartes considered it to be at least as evident that I am a thinking thing as that my thoughts exist — indeed, even more evident.

To further buttress this position Descartes appealed to an intuitive truth that, he claimed, “is very well known by the natural light” (Principles I.11): that “nothingness possesses no attributes nor qualities.”  As thus stated, this certainly appears to be the sort of principle that it would be impossible to deny.  There is nothing to nothing.  But Descartes meant to employ a rather more robust, contrapositive version of this principle: that where there are attributes or qualities there must necessarily be some thing or substance in which those attributes or qualities inhere.  This is to presume that there can be no “free floating” attributes or qualities, and why should we accept that?  More to the point, Descartes wanted to claim that because we find ideas of all things within ourselves, we must know ourselves better than we know anything else, because things are known through knowing their attributes or qualities and while we can doubt that these ideas or qualities represent or inhere in anything that exists outside of us, they are certainly attributes or qualities of ourselves.  But why should we reduce thoughts to attributes or qualities of things rather than consider them to be things in their own right?

Descartes’s answer to both of these questions would have been the same: these are intuitively evident first principles, evident to us “in the natural light.”  When we examine our ideas we simply see, indubitably, that they are imperfect or dependent things that could not exist on their own but that must be “happenings” that are contained “within” something else.  And we just see that this is a special case of the more general rule that attributes or qualities must inhere in some substance and that substances are known as things that possess attributes and qualities.  We see these things so clearly that they cannot be doubted.

This is not the only occasion on which Descartes appealed to a “natural light” that reveals common notions to us.  Just in this one reading section there are two others, at Principles I.18 and I.20.  In those places, appeals to the light of nature play an important part in proofs for the existence of God.  And there are many other appeals to the light of nature both in the Principles and in Descartes other works.  It would not be entirely inappropriate to suspect that Descartes abandoned his method of doubt on these occasions and appealed to the natural light as an oracle, capable of revealing things that could not otherwise be known.  However, a more charitable reading, based on Principles I.6, would have it that the method of doubt is what enables to distinguish between what is really known by the light of nature and what is only the product of juvenile preconceptions.  If it is really known by the natural light, we have no freedom to doubt it.  If it is not, we can.  Descartes maintained that we cannot doubt that qualities and attributes must inhere in some substance.  As we will see, later early modern philosophers were not so sure.

 

Principles I.13-23.  Arguments for the existence of God.  In addition to being certain of the existence of himself as a mental substance, Descartes claimed that we can be certain that there must be a God (and so, incidentally, that there could not be a deceiver, which opens the door to being assured of the results of carefully and repeatedly performed demonstrations and calculation after all, and even to placing some trust in sensory experience).  He devoted considerable attention to this important enterprise and over the course of Principles 13-23 offered three arguments for the existence of God, presenting each later argument as a kind of support for the earlier one.  The arguments are just what they would need to be: arguments that take off from what Descartes considered to be established beyond any doubt: first, the ideas of his own existence within himself, and second the ability to appeal to certain intuitively evident first principles concerning relations between those ideas.  Since the existence of an external world is at this point still in question, Descartes’s arguments are not cosmological or teleological arguments — arguments that attempt to prove that God must have existed as the first cause or designer of the world around us.  The premises are lacking for such arguments.  Instead the arguments appeal exclusively to what we are able to find within ourselves.

 

Principles I.14-16.  The ontological argument.  Descartes’s first argument for the existence of God is based just on appeal to the ideas we find within ourselves and does not rely on any intuitive truths.  Among the ideas we find within ourselves is an idea of God.  And just as, by inspecting ideas like those of a square or a triangle, we can simply perceive that a square has four sides and a triangle three, so, Descartes claimed, when contemplating the idea of God, we can see that such a being must necessarily exist.  Our idea of God is the idea of a supremely perfect being.  But, according to Descartes, existence adds to the perfection of a thing.  This is proven by the fact that, if you were offered a choice between having ten actually existing dollars and ten imaginary dollars, you would choose the actually existing ones.  Your preference for the actually existing ones proves that existence adds to the perfection of a thing.  Consequently, were God to lack existence, God would be less than supremely perfect, which is contrary to what the idea of God tells us.  We must conclude, therefore, that our idea of God is the idea of an existing thing.  Existence is as inseparable from our idea of God as having three sides is from our idea of a triangle, and is intuitive in the same way: by clearly and distinctly perceiving what is contained in the idea.

Arguments for the existence of God of this style did not originate with Descartes.  They are commonly called “ontological” arguments and they have had and continue to have many critics as well as many defenders.  One of the standard objections is that existence ought not to be treated as a “perfection” or a quality that adds to the greatness of a thing.  We can describe an idea as we clearly and distinctly perceive it to be, but it still remains a question whether anything exists that corresponds to the idea as thus defined.  When describing an idea we list the real features or qualities that it exhibits.  But existence is not a real feature or quality.  Saying that something exists does not add to the reality of the idea or make it a different kind of idea, as if an existing dragon were a different species of thing from a non-existing dragon, the way a rational animal is a different species from an irrational animal.  When we say that something exists we are merely adding the information that there is an object in the world that corresponds to the idea; we are not listing any further real quality of the idea itself.  As Immanuel Kant was later to put it, ten existing dollars does not contain one penny more than ten possible dollars.  If we prefer the one to the other, it is not because the one is greater or more perfect in any way, but only because we know that the one has a partner in the external world as well as being a mere idea in the mind.

Descartes seems to have been sensitive to this objection even though he did not think it applies to the case of God.  But he did think that, in other cases, it is legitimate to distinguish between the “essence” of a thing (that collection of properties that is characteristic of a thing and that makes it what it is), and the existence of a thing.  It is only in the case of God that there is reason to take existence to be part of the essence.  In all other cases we consider existence to be separable from essence for the very good reason that we consider it to be possible that we might have simply made the thought up ourselves, by imaginatively taking apart and recombining elements encountered in other experiences to build up something entirely fanciful.

But the case of God is different because God is, so to speak, the ens realissimum or being that is the sum total of all reality.  As the infinite being, the idea of God contains the idea of everything else that is real and positive (imperfections of all sorts being assumed to be the result of a lack of something rather than a positive evil).  It is the original source in which we find the component, partial realities that we take apart and recombine to form our ideas of other things — things that need not correspond to anything that actually exists.  But in the case of God, a clear and distinct perception on the part of the understanding compels the will to assert that the necessity of the actual existence of an object corresponding to the idea of the infinite being is part of what we find in the idea.

A similar point might be made in response to another common objection to the ontological argument: that it could (absurdly) be used to prove the necessary existence of an infinite number of things: a “perfect” island, a “perfect” rabbit, a “perfect” white rabbit, a “perfect” white rabbit with yellow eyes, a “perfect” three-pound white rabbit with yellow eyes, and so on.  Descartes’s reply would be that nothing that is limited or circumscribed in any way can consistently be said to be “perfect.”  The counterexample of the supremely perfect island does not work because that conception is self-contradictory.  To be an island is to be surrounded by water, which means being only finitely extended.  That already means being less than supremely perfect.  An island is also just a clump of earth, lacking powers of vegetation, growth, nutrition, reproduction, self-movement, sensation, reasoning, memory, etc.  So there are a great many ways in which an island is imperfect.  That makes the idea of a supremely perfect island maximally confused — self-contradictory.  If we modify the example by adding perfections to the idea of the island, it stops being an idea of an island and becomes the idea of God.  It is only when we consider the idea of a being that is supremely perfect (and there can only be one such being) that we find a reason to assert existence.  In all other cases, where the thing we conceive is thought to lack some perfection or other.  If it lacks anything at all it is not perfect.  And if it lacks one thing then we cannot say that it must exist in order to be perfect because it is not perfect to begin with.  We would instead need to find something else in that implies that it must exist in order to be what it is.  And we can find no such thing.  It is only in the case of an infinite being that we perceive necessary existene.

 

Principles I.17-19.  The argument from the cause of the objective perfection of ideas.  Mention of the fact that in all other cases we distinguish existence from essence led Descartes to bring up a second argument.  This second argument is specially designed for those whose minds are so weak that they cannot see why, in the case of the divine being, existence is necessarily included in the very idea of the thing.  Rather than simply appeal to what is found in the idea, this second argument appeals to certain intuitive truths, principally the truth that nothing is not something and that nothing cannot give rise to something.

The argument proceeds by noting that we all have an idea of God, even if some of us might wonder whether anything actually exists corresponding to this idea.  It then asks how we could have come to have such an idea.

In the background of this argument is the notion that many of our ideas are like pictures or images of things.  It must be stressed that this is merely a simile and is not to be taken literally.  Sensations of smells, tastes, sounds, hot and cold, and hardness and softness were all ideas for Descartes, but they are obviously not pictures in any literal sense. All the same, like pictures, they are of or about something.  A picture of Caesar is something — if it is an oil painting, it consists of coloured oils smeared on canvas — but it is also of something — an ancient Roman general.  We say, colloquially, that Caesar is “in” the picture insofar as the picture is of Caesar, but this is not literally true.  All that is literally in the picture is coloured oil on canvas.  In the medieval tradition in which Descartes was educated the metaphorical notion of Caesar’s being “in” the picture was explained by saying that Caesar is “in” the picture as the object that the painter intended the picture to represent.  In other words, Caesar is in the picture, not literally, but intentionally or objectively (that is, as an intentional object).  Descartes meant to draw our attention to the fact that much the same thing can be said about ideas.  An idea of an apple, for example, is an idea of something that is red and cool and solid.  But the idea is not itself red or cool or solid.  These qualities or “perfections” are in the idea intentionally or objectively rather than literally.  They are the objects the idea is intended to represent, not properties of the idea itself.

Descartes conveyed this notion by remarking that over and above their “formal perfection,” as things of a certain kind, namely ideas, our ideas picture or represent something else, and this represented object is their “objective perfection.”  Contemporary usage has made Descartes’s point less perspicacious than it was in the 17th century.  Today, when we speak of something as being “objective” we often mean to say that it has some sort of perceiver-independent or mind-independent status.  But this is not at all what Descartes had in mind when he used the expression “objective perfection.”  For Descartes, objective perfection is the collection of real or positive qualities that are represented by an idea — the object the idea is intended to represent.  Rather than referring to what exists outside of the mind, it refers to what is “in” our ideas in the special, intentional sense. Whether these “perfections” also exist in external objects outside of the idea is another question and is certainly not something Descartes wanted to imply when he used the phrase, “objective perfection.”

Descartes proceeded to ask what could be the cause, not just of our ideas considered just as mental states inhering in our minds, but of the particular kinds of content the ideas have.  What could be the cause of their objective perfections?

This is a question we still ask today.  We think that some ideas are crude and simple and that anyone could think of them.  Ideas of simple things like different shades of colour or different degrees of heat or cold are like that.  But other ideas seem, because of their complexity or beauty, to contain something grand that calls for a special explanation.  We are amazed, for example, at how Mozart could have composed his pieces or Einstein formulated the theory of relativity. Yet in doing these things, Mozart and Einstein were at bottom doing nothing different than all of us do all the time: they were simply having ideas.  But because the content of those ideas so much exceeds what the rest of us feel capable of producing, we wonder whether they must not have had some special cause, and we develop theories of genius or genetic endowment or cultural and environmental circumstances to explain their occurrence.

Descartes asked the same question.  He observed a rich variety of ideas in himself: ideas of simple natures, of animals, minerals, and vegetables, of other human beings, of angels and God — even ideas of ideas.  What accounts for the content of these ideas?

There is a certain view of causality that lies behind this question.  Descartes claimed that when a thing comes to be, it must acquire whatever it contains from somewhere.  A blade of grass, for example, must acquire everything it contains from somewhere — from the seed it grew out of, but also from the surrounding earth, air, water, and sunlight.  The sum of things it acquires its properties from just is the “efficient and total cause” of that thing.  That efficient and total cause must either have the properties exhibited by the effect already in it, or must contain something greater than those properties, from which they could be extracted.  As Descartes put it, “all the intricacy” that is found in a thing “must be contained in its cause …; and it must be contained … in actual reality, either formally or eminently” (AT VIIIA 13).

Descartes proceeded to apply this general causal principle to the specific case of ideas.  He claimed that just as, in general, everything that comes to be must have some cause that contains at least as much as is to be found in the thing that comes to be, so every idea must have some cause.  Ideas are, after all, also things that come to be. Moreover, this cause must not just be adequate to account for the coming to be of the idea considered formally as an idea; it must also be adequate to account for how the idea has come to have the content that it does, that is, to depict or represent the object that it represents. To do that, the cause of the idea must actually or literally contain at least as much as is represented by the idea.  Descartes put this point by saying that the cause of the idea must formally or eminently contain at least as much as is to be found objectively in the idea.  “All the intricacy [that] is contained in the idea merely objectively — as in a picture — must be contained in its cause …; and it must be contained not merely objectively or representatively, but in actual reality, either formally or eminently, at least in the case of the first and principal cause.” (AT VIIIA 13)  The cause could not just objectively contain the qualities that the idea contains objectively, since to be objectively in a thing means that the thing is an image or picture of sorts.  If the qualities that are pictured by the idea are themselves only pictured by the object that causes the idea, then that merely pushes the question back.  If the cause itself is just a picture or image, then there must be some more remote cause that it is copying, picturing, or imaging.  Ultimately, there must be some cause that actually or literally (that is, “formally”) contains the properties that are being represented, or that (“eminently”) contains something even more real from which the properties being represented can in turn be extracted.

 

COMMENTARY

We might wonder whether Descartes was entitled to rely on the principles that everything that comes to be must have a cause, and that a cause must contain at least as much as is to be found in its effect.  Many of the cause-effect relations we witness regularly, such as a striking match bursting into flame, a loud sound producing an avalanche, a shaken coke can spraying when opened, or a flick of a switch lighting up a building, at least appear to be cases where the effects are nothing like or contain much more than their causes.  In these cases, something does seem to come out of nothing.  Descartes tried to answer these worries by stipulating that the “total” cause must contain as much as the effect — for example, the cause of the avalanche would have to be considered to be not just the sound, but the precarious position of the snow on the mountainside — but it is not clear that this really helps. After the doubt of Principles I.4, the total cause that I am aware of in the case of a lighting match is just a collection of simple natures, collected together in more complex and compound ideas.  The effect is another such collection.  Look at it as one will, the effect contains simple natures, such as heat and bright light, that are simply not to be found anywhere in the total set of circumstances that go to characterize the cause.

This objection would be greatly mitigated if the corpuscularian or mechanical philosophy of Galileo, Hobbes, Boyle, and Descartes himself were correct.  After all, what chiefly poses the counterexamples to Descartes’s causal principles are cases where sensible qualities like colour and heat suddenly emerge in circumstances where they were previously totally absent, as in the case of striking a match in the Antarctic night.  Such examples are answered by the mechanical philosophy, which claims that light and colours and heat and cold are not things that actually exist other than objectively in our ideas. There is nothing in the outside world that resembles them, though there is something that causes them: namely motion.  And new motion is never created out of nothing, even in the case of the creation of something like fire (think, for example, of Hobbes’s account of fire as emerging when small particles that were violently bouncing and vibrating in cells inside of certain bodies suddenly manage to break free).  It only ever arises as a result of collision with previously moving parts.  So if the mechanical philosophy were correct, then Descartes’s position on causality would be less contrary to the evidence than it appears.  Of course, the truth of the mechanical philosophy would need to be established, and were Descartes to invoke the truth of the mechanical philosophy to underwrite his hypothesis about the nature of causality, he would be making an illegitimate appeal to something that, by his own account, is uncertain.

In Principles I.18 Descartes preferred to rest his position just on the Parmenidean intuition that something cannot come from nothing, and hence that what is more perfect or has more reality cannot come from what is less perfect, since then the excess reality in the effect would have had to come out of nothing.  (An interesting consequence of this intuition is that if heat and light do come out of cold and darkness, then they simply cannot be more perfect or more real.)

But there is a more radical question we might ask:  Why should we suppose that whatever comes into being has to be caused by something?  Why could things not simply pop into existence?  To reply that this would be impossible because then the effect would have been produced by some dark, featureless entity we call “nothing,” and such an entity cannot act or do anything, nor can it contain anything that it could contribute to an effect, is to beg the question.  The question is:  “Why does an effect need to be produced by anything else at all (including a thing called “nothing”)?  Why could it not simply pop into existence?”  To answer this question by saying “because then it would not be produced by anything (i.e., it would be produced by “nothing”) is not to give an answer at all, but simply to repeat the very thing that needs to be proven.

This is a good example of a troubling issue alluded to earlier: the difficulty of distinguishing between clear and distinct perceptions, on the one hand, and juvenile preconceptions on the other. Descartes would have maintained that the principle that a cause must contain at least as much as is to be found in its effect is clearly and distinctly perceived.  But is it, or is it merely a juvenile preconception?

Descartes’s causal principle gives voice to what was in his day a traditional and blindly accepted view of the nature of causality.  We might call this view the containment model.  According to it a cause is not simply a signal event that often or necessarily happens before an effect occurs; it is something that actively produces its effect.  It produces the effect, moreover, by either drawing together some of its own content and excreting this content as its effect, much as a woman gives birth to a child; or by drawing together and reforming surrounding content, as a builder does with bricks, wood, and mortar; or by impressing or imposing or infecting the raw material that already exists in the effect with its content, much as a signet ring impresses its form on the sealing wax, a fire imposes its heat on the surrounding stones, or a diseased person infects others with their disease.  This is not the only way to understand causality, as will be seen later in connection with Hume.

Ironically, Descartes’s own allusions to “eminent” containment challenge this supposedly certain principle and so poses further problems for his argument.

Remark on eminent causality.  Descartes’s causal principle has an untoward implication.  God is supposed to have created the world.  But the world is composed of extended bodies.  If the cause of an effect is supposed to contain at least much reality as is found in the effect, then it would appear to follow that God must also be extended.  But extension is not one of the attributes traditionally ascribed to the Christian God, who is rather supposed to be purely spiritual.

Descartes was not the only Christian philosopher who had to confront this theological difficulty.  Any Christian philosopher who shared Descartes’s views on causality — and that included virtually all the philosophers of the medieval period — had the same problem.  The containment model of causality appears to contradict Christian theology. According to the containment model, if God created extended bodies, God must contain extension.  According to Christian theology, God cannot be extended.

Rather than reject the one or the other of these doctrines, Descartes and his medieval predecessors tried to have things both ways by claiming that, though God does not contain extension, he does contain things that are more perfect than extension.  Extension was supposed to flow from these more perfect qualities without contradicting the principle that the cause must contain at least as much as is to be found in its effect. But it is not clear that this notion can be invoked without giving up the containment model of causality.  If a supposedly more eminent or perfect or real being can produce something it does not itself contain, then, however mean or ignoble that result may be when compared to what is actually present in the more eminent or perfect or real being, it is still something that is not present in the more eminent or perfect or real being.  It must therefore have come to be out of nothing, in violation of the containment model.  In the final analysis, the notion of eminent causality is nothing more than what Bacon would have called an Idol of the Theatre: a piece of jargon used to paper over the existence of a fundamental theoretical inconsistency.

 

Principles I.17-19.  The argument from the cause of the objective perfection of ideas, cont.’d.  Setting these worries aside for the moment, let’s return to Descartes’s second argument from the existence of God.  We all possess an idea of God, that is of an infinitely perfect being.  Some of us may think that while we may have such an idea, it does not follow that any object actually exists corresponding to it.  But, armed with the notion that the cause of an idea must actually contain at least as much as is found in the object of that idea, Descartes asked how we could have come by such an idea.  The cause of the idea of a dragon may not be a dragon, but it has to have all the perfections in it that we find rearranged in our idea of a dragon: shape, size, colour, motion, and so on.  Otherwise, there would be something in the effect that is greater than the cause and this greater reality would have to have come out of nothing which, so Descartes maintained, is clearly impossible.  This is something that people commonly accept, and we see instances of this reasoning around us all the time, from parents who demand to know who gave their children the ideas they have of sex to historians of philosophy who ask what gave a particular philosopher this or that novel idea.  In the 1990’s when the Eastern Block states collapsed, they did so more or less from West to East and a popular theory at the time was that this was due to the fact that television signals from Western countries were being received in East Germany and Poland, giving those people an idea of Western lifestyles that those in the Soviet Union did not have and could not produce on their own, and so making the Germans and Poles less willing to put up with the state of affairs in their countries than the Soviets.

At this point, Descartes was in a position to claim that the idea of God could have nothing less than God as its cause.  He could not have produced this idea himself, he claimed, because, as he was painfully aware, he was not himself supremely perfect, but possessed only limited understanding and a liability to make mistaken judgments.  Given that he was this way, he ought to have been incapable of forming the idea of any more perfect being.  Yet he could.  The idea must therefore have some other cause than himself.  But nothing that falls short of infinite perfection could be the cause of his idea of an infinitely perfect being, either.  Only a supremely perfect being could have given him the idea of a supremely perfect being.  Such a being must therefore exist.

 

Principles I.20-23.  The argument to the cause of the thing that has the ideas.  This argument has not convinced very many people.  Descartes thought that one reason for this might be that we cannot recall a time at which we first received for formed the idea of God.  This might lead some to suppose that the idea does not need any sort of special cause.  Perhaps it is simply “natural.”

Accordingly, over Principles I.20 Descartes complemented his argument by appeal to the cause of our idea with an argument that appeals to the cause of ourselves and of everything we have always found within ourselves.  Granting that we are certain not merely that our ideas (among them perhaps an idea of God) exist, but also that we ourselves exist, we can also inquire into the cause of ourselves.  In giving the argument, Descartes made a third appeal to principles discerned in the light of nature to claim that a being that finds within itself an idea of something more perfect than itself could not have been its own cause.  For, if it were, it would naturally have given itself whatever extra perfections it finds in this idea.  Were I powerful enough to bring myself into existence, I ought to have been powerful enough to give myself some more of the perfections that I think of when I think of an all perfect being.  If I could bring myself into existence out of nothing, I ought surely to be able to do something as easy by comparison as give myself some more perfect knowing powers, so that I would not be infected with the doubts that I find within myself or recall the history of past mistakes that I do. But that is something I manifestly have not managed bring about.  Thus, some more perfect than we are must have created not only our idea of it, but ourselves as well.

 

Principles I.21.  The doctrine of constant creation.  At Principles I.21, Descartes claimed that this causal argument can be made all the more compelling by considering the nature of time.  In the third of his Meditations on First Philosophy he had written, “it is obvious to anyone who pays close attention to the nature of time, that plainly the same force and action are needed to preserve anything at each individual moment that it lasts as would be required to create that same thing anew . . . conservation differs from creation solely by virtue of a distinction of reason” (AT VII 49).  Principles I.21 echoes this doctrine: “the nature of time is such that its parts are not mutually dependent, and never coexist.  Thus, from the fact that we now exist, it does not follow that we shall exist a moment from now.”

When time passes, what exists now, the present, becomes past.  But the past no longer exists.  To say that the present becomes past is to say that it gets destroyed.  But if what exists now gets destroyed in the very next instant by the passage of time, how is it that we still see it continuing from one moment to the next?  Obviously, what got destroyed must have been recreated.  And since the passage of time destroys everything that exists from moment to moment, everything must be constantly recreated from moment to moment.  This is why conservation does not really differ from creation, and why the same force and power is required to preserve a thing in existence as to create it in the first place — preserving it just means constantly recreating it from one moment to the next.

This is called the doctrine of constant creation.  According to it, the world was not just created in the beginning, but must be continually recreated from moment to moment.  Were it not to recreated, it would blink out of existence.

The doctrine of constant creation will be important for a proper understanding of Cartesian physics, and in the hands of Pierre Bayle, it was exploited to buttress a more profound sceptical argument than any Descartes ever envisioned.

In this context, Descartes appealed to the doctrine to make the point that we could not possibly be the causes of our own, continued self-existence.  For if we were, we would have a power, the power to bring something to be out of nothing, that is so vast that surely we ought to have been able to employ it to make ourselves more perfect than we currently are.  The conclusions are twofold:  First, we must have some cause other than ourselves that preserves us in existence from moment to moment.  Second, this cause must also be preserving itself and the whole universe in existence from moment to moment.  And insofar as it is able to do so, it must be employing that power to make itself supremely perfect, since such power must have no bounds and it would certainly want to do so.

 

There are still problems, however.  One is posed by Descartes own claim that whatever ideas we find within ourselves must be considered as qualities or attributes of ourselves (Principles I.11) combined with his admission that it is not in the nature of a finite being to fully comprehend the infinite (Principles I.19).  This would suggest that we simply do not have any sort of adequate idea of an infinitely perfect being.  The best we can manage is to think of things that we ourselves possess or conceive, all of which fall far short of what would be contained in an infinitely perfect being, and none of which require appeal to an infinitely perfect cause if their existence is to be accounted for.  This does not get around the argument from constant creation, which asks how we could continue in existence from moment to moment, and why, if we are the ones responsible for this prodigious feat, we would not do something so much simpler by comparison as create ourselves with enhanced cognitive powers.  But the argument from constant creation poses its own problems.  It countenances a counterexample to the supposedly intuitively evident principle that something cannot come from nothing.  According to the doctrine of constant creation, this is so far from being the case that everything is constantly coming from nothing, being a product of God’s continued recreation of the universe out of nothing from moment to moment — necessarily out of nothing since what exists at any moment is annihilated at the next.  Granted, it is only a supremely powerful being who is being allowed to have this extraordinary power.  But the fact remains: bringing something out of nothing is doable.  So we cannot suppose that it is simply impossible that something should come out of nothing.

That having been said, the view that causes must be like their effects and must transmit something of what they contain to their effects was central to the mechanical philosophy, which maintained that motion in bodies is caused by collision with other moving bodies and that the cause loses as much of its motion as it communicates to the effect.  This would have made the causal principle at the root of his argument a natural preconception for Descartes to uncritically accept.  Ironically, the method of doubt was supposed to root out such infantile prejudices.

 

 ESSAY QUESTIONS AND RESEARCH PROJECTS

 

   1.    Was Descartes entitled to claim that there is no way to distinguish waking from dreaming?

   2.    Could a deceiver who systematically deceives me, and ensures that I never come across any evidence of my mistake, really be a deceiver?

   3.    Was Descartes entitled to claim, at this stage in his argument, that he did not need to have a body in order to be able to understand, affirm, deny, doubt, will, etc.?

   4.    Could an evil genius make me be mistaken about my intuitions?

   5.    Descartes claimed to know that he is a thinking thing.  However, to say that what exists is a “thing” suggests that there is something that bears properties (in this case, that there is something that has thoughts) and that this thing endures over time, perhaps altering in state (i.e., changing its thoughts) over time.  Is there anything in Descartes’s account that might entitle him to affirm that, in addition to the thoughts that he knew must exist, there must be some one substance in which they all inhere?

   6.    Assess the adequacy of Descartes’s attempt to defend his ontological argument for the existence of God against the objections he himself raises to that argument.  Consider whether there are any other, more serious objections he fails to consider and then consider whether he could also answer those objections.

 

   7.    Descartes’s discussion of the formal and objective reality of ideas raises issues of what ideas are and how they refer to objects.  These issues came to be hotly debated in the ensuing years (and have been discussed ever since).  The two chief protagonists in the subsequent debate were Descartes’s younger contemporary and one-time critic, Antoine Arnauld (left, one of the leaders of the Jansenist movement in 17th century French Catholicism), and the Oratarian priest, Nicholas Malebranche (right), who developed a Neo-Cartesian

 

philosophy of his own.  The chief point in dispute between Malebranche and Arnauld was whether ideas are objects of apprehension (the view of Malebranche), or acts whereby objects are apprehended (the view of Arnauld).  The Malebranche/Arnauld dispute has been the subject of extensive scholarly study, but two early papers on the topic are classics that should be read by any student of 17th century philosophy: Robert McRae, “‘Idea’ as a Philosophical Term in the 17th Century,” Journal of the history of ideas 26 (1965): 175-184, and John Yolton, “Ideas and Knowledge in Seventeenth-Century Philosophy,” Journal of the history of philosophy 13 (1975): 145-166. Study these two papers and report on the main results of each.

   8.    Does Descartes have a principled way of distinguishing between what is known by the “light of nature” and what is known by “natural impulse”?

   9.    Consider whether Descartes is in any position to claim to be certain of any of the causal principles he invokes in Principles I.18.  Try to come up with the best argument you can to defend his position and the best argument you can to reject it.  Determine which argument is the strongest.

10.    Descartes’s notion of eminent causality is drawn from medieval philosophy.  Undertake a research project to discover just how this notion was understood by medieval philosophers.  (Note that rather than speak of eminent causality, the medievals might have instead discussed eminent containment of a form, which they would have contrasted with literal exhibition of a form.)  Determine whether the medievals managed to articulate a clear, coherent sense in which it is possible for a thing to contain a form it does not literally exhibit.  Then determine whether Descartes had any right to employ this notion (note that, despite the doubts of Meditations I, he only needed to make a case that it is possible that there might be eminent causes).  If he dids have a right to employ the notion, did he also have a right to make the further claim that he could be the “eminent” cause of his idea of extension?