20

Locke, Essay II.viii.7-26

Primary and Secondary Qualities

 

Over Essay II.viii.7-26 Locke considered the question of how our simple ideas of sensation are related to the objects that produce them. Might the qualities that appear in our ideas also be qualities of bodies that exist outside of us?  Might they at least resemble qualities of bodies?  Or might there be nothing like the qualities of our ideas to be found in bodies?  Alternatively might some qualities of our ideas be qualities of bodies while others are not?

In addressing these questions, Locke divided our simple ideas of sensation into three different classes:

i) ideas of solidity, extension or bulk, and their various modifications,

ii) ideas of sensible qualities like colour, smell, taste, sound, heat and cold,

iii) ideas of pleasure and pain.

He proceeded to point out that people have generally supposed that the qualities represented by our type (i) and (ii) ideas are more or less exact replicas of properties existing in external objects, and that we only have these ideas because external objects have somehow managed to impress us with these qualities.  In contrast, people have generally supposed that type (iii) ideas of pleasure and pain do not resemble anything to be found in external objects, even though they are also caused by these objects. Type (iii) ideas are supposed to exist only in the mind, and only when they are perceived.

Locke’s main point over this part of the Essay is that while the tradition is right about type (i) and type (iii) ideas, it is wrong about type (ii) ideas.

The main reason Locke had to offer for this position is given in Essay II.viii.11.  Locke there claimed that the only way in which one body can be conceived to act upon another is by impact.  This requires us to ascribe motion, solidity, and figure to bodies, since to impact one another bodies have to be moving and solid, and to be solid they have to take up a space of some figure.  However, it also means that we must consider all of our ideas to be products of the motion, solidity and figure of bodies, rather than to be due to some quality in the bodies that bleeds out of them and into our sense organs.  For, if all action of one body on another requires impact, then the action of bodies on our sense organs must also require impact; and that means that bodies must be supposed to affect us through being moving, solid and figured, and not through transmitting other qualities.

 

QUESTIONS ON THE READING

    1.     Explain the difference between qualities and ideas.

Reading Note: In both II.viii.7 and II.viii.10 the phrase “in the subject” occurs.  You should understand this phrase to be a reference to the object outside us, not to the perceiving subject.  Thus, II.viii.7 is a reference to “resemblance of something inherent in the external object,” and II.viii.10 to “real qualities in the external object.” Locke used “subject” here in the sense of “subject of investigation.”

    2.     What features must a quality have if it is to be considered primary?

    3.     How do the secondary qualities differ from the primary, if at all?

    4.     How do the tertiary qualities differ from the primary and the secondary, if at all?

    5.     How is it possible for one body to act on another?

    6.     Given that external objects are not only not united to our minds but even sometimes set at some distance from us, by what means do we come to perceive their original qualities?

    7.     When Locke wrote in II.viii.15 that “the Ideas, produced in us by these Secondary Qualities, have no resemblance of them at all,” what were the ideas he was referring to, and what were the secondary qualities that he had in mind?

    8.     What produces the idea of the motion and shape of a piece of manna in us?  What produces the ideas of sickness, acute pains, and gripings in those who have eaten a piece of manna?  What produces our ideas of the whiteness and sweetness of the manna?

    9.     What is the only effect that the pounding of an almond can produce in the almond?  What effect does the pounding of an almond produce in us when we perceive it?

10.     Under what conditions do we have an idea of the thing as it is in itself?

 

NOTES ON THE READING

The topic of Essay II.viii.7-26 does not fit very well with the idea of doing a critique of the human knowing powers by means of the “historical, plain method” of investigating the origin of our ideas, their nature, and the conclusions that can be drawn from them.  Instead of starting from ideas and determining what can be inferred from them, Locke here simply presupposed the existence of external objects, presupposed that these objects affect us, and went on to inquire how our ideas might be related to them.

However, what Locke later described as “this little excursion into natural philosophy” (II.viii.22) is not entirely unjustified if we consider that, unlike Descartes, he did not think that he first needed to prove the existence of bodies from absolutely certain first principles.  For him, it is enough that it should be likely that there are bodies.  Granting that it is indeed likely, the question of the relation between our ideas and bodies naturally arises, and Locke thought it would be wise, right at the outset, to get clear about which features of our ideas might even possibly be supposed to be resemblances of qualities in bodies.  This is especially the case since, as he thought, people have generally taken things like colours, heat and cold to be qualities in bodies when in fact they can be nothing more than ideas in us.

He began by drawing a distinction between ideas in us and qualities in bodies.

 

Whatsoever the Mind perceives in it self, or is the immediate object of Perception, Thought, or Understanding, that I call Idea; and the Power to produce any Idea in our mind, I call Quality of the Subject wherein that power is.  [II.viii.8]

 

The inference seems solid enough.  If there are ideas in us and we are not ourselves responsible for producing them, then there must be something in things other than us that is.  Consider whatever it is in a thing that does this to be a quality of that thing.

But what might such qualities be?  Locke needed to come up with some sort of test for discriminating which, among the various things we find in our simple ideas, might resemble qualities actually existing in bodies.  He fixed on the same criteria Newton was to identify in Rule 3.

 

Qualities thus considered in Bodies are, First such as are utterly inseparable from the Body, in whatever estate soever it be; such as in all the alterations and changes it suffers, all the force can be used upon it, it constantly keeps; and Such as sense constantly finds in every particle of Matter [that] has bulk enough to be perceived, and the Mind finds inseparable from every particle of Matter, though less than to make itself singly be perceived by our Senses [II.viii.9]

 

Compare Newton’s claim that “the qualities of bodies [that] admit neither intensification nor remission of degrees, and [that] are found to belong to all bodies within the reach of our experiments, are to be esteemed the universal qualities of all bodies whatsoever.”  Newton’s requirement that qualities not admit of intensification or remission of degrees is reflected in Locke’s that a quality be “such as in all the alternations and changes it suffers, all the force can be used upon it, it constantly keeps.”  And Newton’s requirement that a quality be found to belong to all bodies within the reach of our experiments is reflected in Locke’s that a quality be “Such as sense constantly finds in every particle of Matter [that] has bulk enough to be perceived.”

We might wonder why Locke thought these are useful criteria for identifying the “first” qualities of bodies.  After all, it is not as if we see the bodies themselves and so can discern from experience that all bodies in fact have certain qualities and that no process in nature ever destroys those qualities.  We can only see our ideas.  Unfortunately, Locke provided us with no enlightenment on this score.  The most likely answer is that he may have thought that if any features of our ideas could be ascribed to bodies, they would be those that are present in all of our ideas of bodies.

Applying this rule, Locke determined that all bodies must be solid (for reasons already considered in the previous chapter), and also that they must be extended.  For, even though bodies may be divided, division does not destroy their extension, but merely cuts it up into separate pieces that can be moved apart from one another.  Unlike Newton, however, Locke did not list gravitational mass among the qualities that must be admitted among all bodies (action at a distance seems to have been simply too much for him to accept, though in later editions of the Essay he silenced his objections to it in deference to Newton’s results), and he speculated that inertial mass and hardness may be simply modifications of solidity (II.iv.5).

Insofar as bodies are admitted to be solid and extended, they must also have all the qualities that arise from the ways solidity and extension can be modified.  They must have inertia (which Locke took to be an effect of solidity [II.iv.5]), hardness, figure, size, orientation, and mobility, and they must be divisible into parts.  These parts in turn must have their own inertia, hardness, figures and sizes, and depending on how they are ordered and interlinked in composite bodies, they create different textures.

There is another reason for concluding that all bodies must have qualities of solidity and extension.  Recall that Locke defined a quality as a power in a body to produce an idea in us.  Locke also took it to be “manifest”            that the only way that one thing can act on another is by impulse, that is, communication of motion as a result of impact or collision (Essay II.viii.11).  (Hence, his inability to accept gravitational mass among the primary qualities.)  It would have to follow that insofar as bodies have powers to produce ideas in us, those powers must involve impulse.  But impulse presumes motion and solidity, and motion presumes some number of things placed at different locations over time, situated in some way with respect to one another to constitute a shape of a certain size.  So all of the qualities that Locke identified as primary are necessary if bodies are to exert a power to bring about ideas in us in the only way Locke considered action to be possible, by impulse.

Looking at things in this way led Locke to conclude that people are in fact right to take their type (i) ideas to be reflections or resemblances of qualities that are actually in bodies.  (Interestingly, Locke did not, as was speculated in the previous chapter concerning solidity, take our type (i) ideas to be direct perceptions of the primary qualities in bodies.  Instead, he here took them to be images or resemblances of such qualities.  “The Ideas of primary Qualities of Bodies, are Resemblances of them, he wrote, and their Patterns do really exist in the Bodies themselves,” he wrote at II.viii.15, suggesting that the idea is one thing, the quality another, even though they may resemble.  II.viii.7 similarly worries which of our ideas are “Images and Resemblances” of qualities in bodies, not which are direct perceptions of those very qualities as they exist in bodies.)  However, Locke did not think that the solidity, shape, and motion of bodies are directly communicated to the mind, to produce our type (i) ideas.  Because he took it to be “manifest” that the only way bodies can bring about ideas in us is by impulse he could not countenance any direct connection between external objects and our minds, particularly in the case of vision.  Impulse requires contact, and bodies are not in contact with our minds, or even with our brains. Indeed, some of the bodies that we sense are set at quite some distance from us.  Reflecting on this fact, Locke concluded that if we nonetheless get type (i) ideas from these bodies, it must be because they emit or reflect a stream of insensibly small particles towards our sense organs.  But even the objects of touch do not touch our brains, but only the exterior surface of our sense organs, which produces alterations in the way the nerves or the particles flowing through the nerves are moving.  These motions are transmitted to the brain and the result of this process, a motion of the parts of the brain, likely bears only the most remote similarity to the body that originally caused it.  However, Locke supposed that the particular ideas of extension and solidity that are produced in the mind when particular motions occur in the brain do, happily or because of divine providence, at least bear some degree of resemblance to the macroscopic shapes, motions, and solidity of the bodies that originally affected us.   Very often, the shapes we see are distortions of the actual shapes of the objects, and the distortions are mathematically related to the actual shapes and are distorted in the ways that they are in accord with constant laws, the laws observed by painters when depicting how the shapes and sizes of objects are changed as a consequence of distance and perspective.

Locke went on to claim that while our type (i) ideas are at least “resemblances” of qualities in bodies, it is a vulgar error to suppose that the type (ii) ideas also resemble qualities in bodies.  In fact, he claimed, we have more reason to suppose that they are like the type (iii) ideas — that they only exist in us and only exist when perceived, though they are caused by something that endures in external objects independently of being perceived.

It is important to understand the path of Locke’s argument.  Locke did not claim that we can know that our type (i) ideas are resemblances of qualities in bodies, but that our type (ii) ideas are not.  He rather argued that we have a number of good reasons to doubt that our type (ii) ideas resemble any qualities actually inhering in bodies.  These same reasons do not, however, apply to our type (i) ideas (Essay II.viii.21 contrasts the different sensations of heat and cold that we can get when we immerse a hot and a cold hand in the same bucket of water with the sensations that we have of the figures of bodies, which according to Locke never vary regardless of what state our hands are in).  Therefore, while we have reason to doubt that our type (ii) ideas resemble qualities in bodies, we have no reason to doubt that our type (i) ideas do so.  This does not mean that we can claim to know or be certain that our type (i) ideas do resemble qualities in bodies.  At best it means that we have no good reason to doubt this claim, and so can believe it is probably true.

Locke offered five main reasons for doubting that type (ii) ideas resemble qualities in bodies.  The first is to be found at II.viii.16.  Locke there observed that type (ii) ideas can, as it were, shade off into type (iii) ideas.  Warmth and cold, for example, are type (ii) ideas that turn into pain as they are intensified.  This is an indication that type (ii) ideas cannot really be distinct from type (iii) ideas.  They are simply lesser degrees of the same phenomena that are present in more intense degrees in our type (iii) ideas.  But everyone is agreed that type (iii) ideas exist only as ideas in us and are not qualities in bodies.  If the type (ii) ideas are simply less intense degrees of the type (iii), then they ought to exist only as ideas in us as well.

Locke’s second argument is alluded to in the last clause of II.viii.16 and laid out more fully in II.viii.18.  (II.viii.17 does not offer an argument but simply further describes the theory and is passed over here.)  At the close of paragraph 16 he observed that if the only way change can occur is by impulse (as was claimed in II.viii.11), then the only way any ideas whatsoever, including our ideas of sensible qualities, can be brought about in us is by motions of solid, shaped parts.  But if all that needs to exist in order to cause our ideas of sensible qualities is the motion of shaped and solid particles, then it would be extravagant to suppose that bodies must also have qualities that resemble colours, smell, heat and cold, and other sensible qualities.  II.viii.18 argues for this same point by means of an extended discussion of a piece of manna.  (Manna was an 18th century medicinal concoction used to induce nausea and vomiting.  It was white and sweet and was baked up in pans like cake and then cut up in squares.)  Locke’s point is that the type (i) ideas we get of the manna’s shape and motion are supposed to be the result of the aggregate shape and motion of its insensibly small parts.  Similarly, the type (iii) ideas we get of pain in the guts are supposed to be the result of exactly the same cause: the motion of the insensibly small, shaped and solid parts that go to make up the manna, acting on our intestines.  Why, therefore, asked Locke, should we suppose that the whiteness and sweetness must alone have some other, unique cause, qualities actually resembling whiteness and sweetness?  It is not as if it is any more mysterious how colourless, tasteless particles could produce ideas of colour and taste than it is how they could produce ideas of cramping and pain, yet we have no problem accepting the latter consequence.  By parity of example we ought to accept the former.

Locke’s third argument is given over II.viii.19, and turns on the observation that our type (ii) ideas can disappear even though the bodies remain and are not thought to have undergone any alteration. Locke instanced the mineral, porphyry, which looks to be red and white, but which does not have those qualities in the dark.  Since the red and white disappear in the dark, but we do not think that the porphyry is destroyed or altered by shutting off the light, we must conclude that these colours are not really qualities in the body, porphyry, but rather results of the way light affects our senses.  At the very least, they are not qualities bodies have to have in order to be conceivable and that they have to retain through all eventualities.

Locke’s fourth argument is found at II.viii.20.  He there observed that operations that can only plausibly be supposed to change the shapes, arrangements, and motions of the insensibly small parts of bodies lead us to have different type (ii) ideas.  Pounding, for instance, is an operation that can only be supposed to break the extension of a body up into a number of separately movable parts, and so make it softer.  But pounding also changes the colour and taste of an almond.  Since all that pounding can really do is alter the almond’s texture and hardness, the changed taste and colour must be merely effects of the changes in the texture and hardness on our senses of vision and taste, and not independently existing qualities in the bodies at all.

Locke’s final argument is found at II.viii.21 and takes the form of an inference to the best explanation.  He there observed that the same body can simultaneously give us different, incompatible type (ii) ideas. The same bucket of water, for instance, can simultaneously feel warm to a cold hand and cold to a warm one.  Locke pointed out that it is difficult to account for this fact on the supposition that our ideas of colour or heat and cold are caused by resembling qualities that migrate into us from the bodies that affect us.  Since the ideas are incompatible, both cannot simultaneously exist in the object.  At least one of them must be merely an idea in us and not a quality in the body. But which one is the real one and where does the unreal one come from and how do we know that the real one does not come from the same sort of causes that produce the unreal one rather than from a resembling quality in the object?  All of these difficult questions are avoided, Locke claimed, if we accept an alternative theory.  If we take the colour and the degree of temperature to be merely ideas produced in us as a result of bodies hitting our sense organs, then we can take the previously existing state of the sense organ to enhance or impede the motion and so alter the character of the sensation that is communicated to the brain.  And altered sensations can be expected to produce different ideas in the mind. Thus, taking type (ii) ideas to be produced in us by the impact of solid, moving parts provides a better explanation of the phenomena of perceptual relativity than does the supposition that they are caused by resembling qualities in the bodies.

Summing up all of these considerations, Locke claimed that there are three types of qualities in bodies, and three types of ideas in us:

First, there are primary qualities in bodies.  These qualities are solidity, extension, and their modifications.  When bodies are aggregated together in large enough numbers to build up composites of sufficient size to be visible or tangible, our type (i) ideas can be considered to be resemblances of the macroscopic solidity, size, shape, and motion of the composite bodies.  However, when the parts composing an object are too small for us to be able to perceive, or when they lie below an opaque surface that has not been anatomized, our ideas are less accurate.

Locke considered that in addition to the primary qualities of extension, solidity, and their modes, bodies also have a further set of qualities.  He called these qualities powers.  When we consider what bodies can do to us, we get the idea that they have the power to bring about ideas of sensation in us, and when we consider what they can do to one another, we get the idea that they have the power to change one another.  If all motion is due to impact, these powers must ultimately arise from something solid, shaped, and moving hitting something else.  But when we cannot see what it is in bodies that brings about these effects, our ideas of the powers in things are only “relative.”  The power is really some arrangement of solid, shaped, moving, particles.  But since this arrangement of particles is invisible, we identify the power relative to its sensible effects.

It is particularly important to distinguish between secondary qualities as they are in bodies, and type (ii) or non-resembling ideas as they are in us.  Colours, smells, tastes, and so on are not secondary qualities. They are type (ii) ideas brought about by the secondary qualities of bodies.  As effects of the secondary qualities in objects, which are powers to affect us arising from the insensibly small bulk, figure, number, situation, and motion of particles, they may serve as “relative” ideas of those powers, and this can lead to some confusion.  Since we can only think of the different powers by referring to their effects, not by directly discerning the powers themselves, we tend to substitute our ideas of the effects in the place of that of the powers, of which we have no idea.  This can happen easily and inadvertently in language, where it is simply easier to talk about the “redness” in a body than to employ a circumlocution like “the power in the body to bring about the idea of red in us.”  Locke warned us that he himself would often speak this way, even though he knew better.  We need to keep in mind, therefore, that even though he may on many occasions speak as though he takes colours, scents, tastes, and the like to be secondary qualities in bodies, his considered position is that the secondary qualities are powers due to the arrangement of solid, shaped, and moving parts and do not resemble our type (ii) ideas in any way.  If they resemble anything, it is our type (i) ideas.  To confuse colours, smells, tastes and the rest with secondary qualities in bodies is to commit just the error Locke was attempting to expose over II.viii.7-26.

 

 

Essay II ix.1-4,8-9; x.1-2; xi,1,4,6,8,9,15,17

Perception and other Simple Ideas of Reflection

 

For Locke, in addition to the ideas that we get from sense, which refer to objects outside us, there are ideas we get from reflection on the operations of our own minds.  It is through these ideas that we first become conscious of what our own minds do to the ideas they have previously received. Through them, we learn how the mind processes ideas to generate knowledge, belief, opinion, fantasy, and even experience itself.  Essay II.ix-xi is devoted to an examination of some of the main ideas of reflection and the operations they refer to.

These main operations are perceiving, remembering, discerning and comparing, compounding and repeating, naming, and abstracting.

 

QUESTIONS ON THE READING

    1.     Can we have ideas that go unnoticed by us?

    2.     What is the idea immediately imprinted on the mind when we see a black or golden globe?

    3.     What makes it “evident” that this is all there is to the immediate idea?

    4.     What was Molyneux’s question and what was his reason for answering this question in the negative?

    5.     What moral did Locke draw from Molyneux’s negative answer to this question?

    6.     Explain Locke’s distinction between the role played by “perception of sensation” and “idea of judgment” in visual perception.  What is immediately perceived as a consequence of sensation and what is judged?

    7.     What is wrong with viewing memory as a storehouse for ideas we have had in the past?  What is memory if not a storehouse?

    8.     How is it that particular ideas can be made to become general? 

 

NOTES ON THE READING

Perceiving consists in attending to the effects our senses convey from objects to the brain.  Locke maintained that, unless the mind actively attends to or “perceives” these effects, ideas will generally not arise from sensation.  There are exceptions — bright lights, fast moving objects, cuts, burns, pinches, and loud noises tend to intrude on the mind, draw its attention, and force it to form corresponding ideas of colour, motion, pain, and sound.  But objects can often have an influence on our senses and brains that goes unnoticed and does not lead the mind to have any perceptions.  This is readily exemplified by the case of our sensations of pressure and gravity.  Up until this moment, you have likely not been aware of the feeling of your chair or the ground pressing up on you from below.  Yet the chair and the ground have all along been having an influence on your sense of touch, and your sense of touch has all along been transmitting something to your brain as a consequence of being so affected.  But until you chose to attend to them, those sensations did not produce any ideas of solidity or pressure in your mind.  In this case, your ideas are not simply passively received as a result of stimulation of your sense organs, but depend on a special effort of attention.  That act of attention, whether forced upon us by the violence of the sensation of the product of an effort, is what Locke called perceiving.

Note that Locke did not define perception as the operation of attending to ideas that already exist, unnoticed, in the mind.  The process of perceiving or attending is required to bring ideas into being.  If that process is not performed, the sense organs can still transmit motions or impressions into the brain and those motions and impressions will exist in the brain.  But they will not cause ideas. They cause ideas only with the cooperation of the perceptual faculty of the mind.  This cooperation can sometimes be compelled (as in the case of very strong sensations, as noted earlier), but if it is not compelled, ideas will simply not be created, even though the appropriate impressions and motions exist in the brain. There can be no unperceived ideas, therefore.  Ideas only exist insofar as they are perceived.

Locke went on to note that there is much less happening in perception than many suppose.  This is because acts of perception can be overlaid with judgments from which they have not been properly distinguished.

Usually, when we judge, the act of judging is explicitly a two-stage process.  There is something that is given to us in perception as information or premises, and then a conclusion is drawn from this information.  We are perfectly aware that the information is one thing and the conclusion drawn from the information something quite different.  However, in cases where we have been called upon to make the same judgment over and over again, the judgment can become so automatic that we are not aware of making it.  We get the information by perception, make the judgment, and then forget the information we based the judgment on, and forget the act of judgment and just think of the conclusion, so that it seems to us as if we are simply perceiving the conclusion, rather than perceiving the original information and then judging that it entails the conclusion.

Locke gave an example.  A sensation is transmitted from the senses to the brain.  The mind attends to this sensation.  In very young children, attention to this particular type of influence naturally and originally produces the idea of a flat circle, variously coloured.  However, children discover as they grow up that their visual ideas of flat circles, variously coloured, are associated with tangible ideas of globes, and these globes are seen, upon being turned about, to actually be of a uniform colour.  As a result of this experience, an act of judgment intrudes to influence our perception.  In adults the original idea of a flat circle variously coloured is taken to be a sign of a uniformly coloured globe and the transition from the one idea to the other is so easy and rapid that the initially received idea is transformed into the associated idea.  The operation is quite extraordinary, when you think that it is quite difficult to convince adults that they see anything other than a uniformly coloured globe.  They are so little aware of really seeing something quite different and judging from that appearance that they can hardly be convinced that they do not immediately see a uniformly coloured globe.  It is only when they are forced to do something like paint a picture of the globe that they suddenly discover, as they attempt to replicate the exact appearance in coloured paint on canvas, that globes are not uniformly coloured and that cubes are not seen to have three square faces (on the visible side, when viewed from an oblique angle).

In giving this example Locke supposed that we originally see in just two dimensions.  This is something that he took to have been made evident by the practice of painters. Locke seems to have thought that when we go to paint, we are forced to attend more closely to what we really see than we normally do.  Painters who go to paint a golden or jet black globe actually see, upon close inspection of this object, that it is not in fact of a uniform colour, but that the colour shades from bright to dark over various parts.  Then, when they go to replicate this actual appearance on canvas, they discover that their painting, despite being made of varying colours placed on a flat surface, actually looks rounded and uniformly coloured, like a uniformly coloured globe, whereas if they had made it all one colour, it would have looked flat and circular.

Something similar happens with cubes.  We define cubes as three dimensional figures enclosed by six squares set perpendicular to one another.  And this is what they feel like to the touch.  It is also what we naively think they look like.  But it is impossible to make an accurate model of a three dimensional object on a two dimensional surface, like a canvas.  So it ought to be impossible to draw or paint a cube.  However painters discover, perhaps by setting up a fine, wire grid before their eyes, drawing squares on canvas, and then copying the appearance of a cube seen through the wire grid onto canvas, that cubes are not actually seen to have the shapes they are felt to have.  They are seen in perspective.  And when this perspective appearance is reproduced on canvas, the drawing on the two-dimensional surface takes on an appearance of depth in three dimensions.

 

Durer_Perspective

 

Durer Perspective2

 

Woodcuts by Albrecht Dürer, illustrating the use of devices to assist us in drawing what we actually see so as to be able to properly represent objects in perspective.  The spire in the top diagram is necessary for the draughtsman to keep the eye constantly positioned at the same point while viewing through the grid.

 

This experience convinces us that the sensations we originally receive from vision must be like what the painter paints onto canvas. Painters are forced by their craft to paint what they really see.  And we, who look attentively at paintings and see how they lead us to, as we say, “perceive” depth, discover that we are not really perceiving at all, but making judgments based on what is really there, which is not in depth at all, but flat.  The features painters put into paintings must be the very features of the original visual ideas that lead us to infer depth.

If Locke was right about this, then those who have not yet had the relevant experiences should still see the original visual ideas without the modifications our experience subsequently leads us to impose on them.  Thus, very young children should see in only two dimensions.

This is a controversial issue, and it touches on a dispute between Locke and Descartes.  Descartes shared Locke’s supposition that we originally see in only two dimensions. But, when discussing the means whereby we come to visually perceive depth in his Optics, he had declared that some of these means involve “as it were an innate geometry.”  That is, Descartes had supposed that we are simply innately so constituted that, on the occasion of experiencing certain two-dimensional visual ideas, we automatically judge their three-dimensional significance.

Locke’s rejection of innate knowledge did not dispose him to accept Descartes’s account of depth perception.  In opposition to Descartes, he wanted to insist that it is only after we have discovered through experience that certain visual ideas correspond to certain tangible ideas that we are enabled to make judgments concerning visual depth. Unfortunately, Locke and Descartes could not resolve their dispute by introspection.  None of us is any longer in a position to remember how things originally looked to us in the first weeks after birth, or whether we had to learn to associate two-dimensional and chromatic features of our infantile visual experiences with distances outwards along the depth axis.  Neither could the dispute be resolved by approaching very young children and asking them whether they are able to see depth.  By the time children have acquired the verbal and intellectual abilities to understand the question, they are too old to remember what their original visual experiences were like.

 

The Molyneux Question.  This last reflection led Locke into a fascinating digression on what adults, blind since birth, but intellectually sophisticated, able to communicate, and familiar with geometrical concepts learned from the sense of touch would tell us upon acquiring the power of vision. One of his friends, William Molyneux, had earlier posed a question on this topic — a question that has since become one of the central topics of perceptual psychology.  What would happen, Molyneux asked Locke, if a blind person, who had learned by touch to distinguish between a cube and a sphere were made to see and then shown a cube and a sphere?  Would the blind person be able to tell which was the cube and which the sphere just by looking at them, without first touching them?

Both Molyneux and Locke speculated that the answer to this question would have to be no.  They thought that the spatial features of visual experience are not enough like those of tactile experience to lead a previously blind person to be able to confidently declare what objects they are seeing just based on the visual appearance of those objects.  The previously blind person might see two dimensionally extended coloured patches that are in fact circular or square in the sense of having a circumference everywhere equidistant from the center or having four equal sides and four equal angles.  But Locke and Molyneux did not think that this means that the previously blind person would understand their visual experience in all the same ways that we do — that they would straightforwardly take it to be an experience of the all the same objects that we do.  This is because the objects of visual experience are not simply seen but inferred from what is seen, and the previously blind person has not yet learned how to draw those inferences from what is seen to the nature of the objects responsible for that appearance.  The previously blind person would not be able to identify distances of the parts of objects outwards from one another in the direction of depth, and so would not see three dimensional objects like cubes and spheres, much less infer that they are uniformly coloured.  Consequently, when confronted by something like the variation in colour of a globe, the previously blind person might draw distinctions between colour patches where we see just one uniform colour.  And vision would present the previously blind person with nothing analogous to the tactile sensation experienced when touching a cube.  We can feel all six faces at once, but we cannot see them, and the faces we do see may be seen in perspective, which for anyone who accepts that we see in only two dimensions means that they may not be seen as square or made of sides of equal lengths.  As Molyneux put it, the previously blind person is in no position to infer that, simply because something looks to have some shape it would also be felt to have some shape — particularly if the thing looks to have a two-dimensional shape but the question asks about a three-dimensional shape it does not look to have, and if the two-dimensional shape that the object looks to have is a function of where the previously blind person understands the boundaries between differently coloured regions to be drawn.

We have all had the experience that things that feel a certain way do not always look the way they feel.  For example, a straight pencil looks bent when half inserted in a glass of water.  Solid objects cast different images on the eyes depending on how they are turned.  What appears smooth, small, and round from a distance may look craggy, large, and square from close up.  Any object looks to have the shape of a dot if viewed from a sufficient distance under sufficient illumination.  And so on.  But even if the previously blind person were to make the leap to suppose that because objects look to have a certain shape that they would be felt to have that shape as well, the person might well end up describing their visual experience in very different terms than we do, because the two-dimensionality of visual experience is more apparent to them than to us, and because the ways different colours can fall on same surfaces and same colours on different surfaces might lead them to draw figure/background distinctions in a different way than we do.  Consequently, when asked “which is the cube and which the sphere” when nothing they see looks to them like either a cube or a sphere, they would quickly get the idea that objects must look very different from the way they feel, and would hesitate to answer the question with any confidence.

We might ask what would happen if the blind person were told in advance that objects seen from close up generally look the way they feel, or that each point of the three dimensional objects of touch projects onto the visual field by lines drawn from that point, intersecting at the center of the eyeball, and hitting a concave surface of the back of the eye behind that point, so that the sensory stimulus originally produced by visual objects is a concave, two-dimensional projection of those three-dimensional objects.  Locke and Molyneux would probably answer that in that case the experiment would be corrupted and nothing would be learned from it.  Molyneux’s question was whether someone newly made to see would immediately perceive the same objects we do or would see something so different from those objects that it would take a guess or an inference to arrive at an answer.  If you tell the blind person in advance everything that they need to know in order to make a judgment about which object is which, then you won’t be able to tell whether they are just immediately seeing or instead drawing an inference from what they immediately see.

Those who have since considered Molyneux’s question have often forgotten the context in which it was asked, and the presuppositions about the nature of visual experience that Locke and Molyneux carried to their study of that question.  For instance, Leibniz, writing a bit later, claimed that the blind person ought to be able to associate the prickly feel of a cube with the existence of angles in the square colour patch experienced in vision and so discriminate the visual cube from the visual sphere on first sight.  And Reid, a generation after that, maintained that Nicholas Saunderson (a famous English mathematician and geometer, who was blind, but understood the laws of geometrical projection very well), would be able to tell which was which as long as he was told how light rays are reflected from objects and refracted onto the retina by the lens of the eye.  Both Leibniz and Reid missed the point that Molyneux was not asking whether the previously blind person could make an educated guess or a correct judgment.  Molyneux and Locke were trying to get an answer to the question of what the previously blind person would immediately see, not what they would be inclined to guess or judge about what they saw.

Other philosophers and psychologists, beginning with Berkeley and Condillac, have wondered whether the previously blind person would at first be able to see any shapes, or even any spatial order of colour points at all.  Molyneux might have welcomed that question as an even more compelling way of making the point that there is so little affinity between visual and tactile experience that a newly sighted person could not confidently claim to be able to perceive objects by vision.  But Locke might also have seen it as a worrying challenge to his position on primary qualities.  If the objects of vision are effectively not immediately seen to be in space at all, then extension and motion cannot be assumed to be universal qualities of all the objects of sensation.  And since solidity cannot be understood apart from motion and extension (since it has to do with resistance to entry of a moving object into a space), nothing is left that could be a primary quality.

Locke’s purpose in raising the Molyneux question was programmatic.  “This I have set down, and leave with my Reader[s],” he wrote towards the close of Essay II.ix.8, “as an occasion for [them] to consider, how much [they] may be beholding to experience, improvement, and acquired notions, where [they] think, [they have] not the least use of, or help from them.”  Over subsequent parts of Essay II, Locke intended to argue that a number of ideas that Descartes and others had supposed to be immediately perceived by a direct inspection on the part of the understanding    ideas like those of substance, infinity, intelligible extension, and identity    are in fact built up by mental operations (such as compounding, comparing, and abstracting) from more primitive ideas that are  originally given through sensation.  The consideration of the Molyneux question served as a sort of preparative for that argument.  Locke’s thought was that if we could be led by consideration of the Molyneux question to appreciate that a significant number of the ideas that we think are directly and immediately perceived by us are actually worked up by unnoticed mental operations performed upon more primitive and simpler ideas, then we would be more receptive to what he had to say in the remainder of Essay II.

But whatever opportunities the question might have offered to Locke to make other points, it is also troubling.  It is not clear what originally motivated Molyneux to ask his question, but the fact is that what Locke said about visual perception in the first edition of Essay II.ix.8 does not sit well with what he had said at Essay II.v about ideas of space and extension coming from more than one sense, and at Essay II.viii.21 about the distinction between primary and secondary qualities.  Locke seems not to have noticed this and to have viewed Molyneux’s question as a further illustration of what he had to say at II.ix.8 rather than as a challenge to his earlier claims.  But if the fact that the same bucket of water can appear warm to a cold hand and hot to a cold hand entails that heat and cold must be merely type (ii) ideas in us rather than primary qualities of bodies, then by parity of example the fact that the same object can appear round to the touch and flat to they eye should entail that round and flat must be merely type (ii) ideas in us rather than primary qualities of objects.  And the same object does appear round to the touch and flat to the eye if we accept Molyneux’s claim that the visual and tactile appearances of the same object are so different that a person newly made to see could not, at first sight, apply the same names to both.  If shape, size, and position are not qualities that are common to both sight and touch, but visual shape is distinct from tangible shape, visual size from tangible size, and visual position different from tangible position, then with what right do we consider these to be qualities of objects rather than features special to specifically visual and tactile ideas?  Had this been what motivated Molyneux’s question, Locke might have had a harder time endorsing Molyneux’s negative answer — or at least noticed a need to reconcile a negative answer with his other views.

There were no actual tests of the Molyneux question made in Locke’s day, though a generation later an English physician, William Chesselden, removed cataracts from a boy’s eyes and made careful observations on the boy’s reactions — observations that appeared to confirm Locke’s and Molyneux’s positions on the question.  Subsequent work has been more ambiguous and has tended, if anything, to establish Berkeley’s and Condillac’s conjecture that visual experience is far more complex and multi-faceted than Locke and Molyneux had imagined.

 

Contemplation and Memory.  Locke noted that we have a capacity to hold an idea we have once perceived in mind even after the sensation that caused it is no longer occurring in the brain.  Locke called this capacity contemplation.

Memory, in contrast to contemplation, is the capacity to have ideas that have been perceived in the past.  Obviously, we do remember things, and we do so all the time.  But memory is an extremely difficult operation to account for.  There is something almost paradoxical about it.  We cannot remember something off in the past the way we see something off in the distance, by just looking and seeing it faint and obscure on the horizon.  For the past no longer exists.  Given this fact, it is tempting to say that what we do is contemplate some left over trace or echo of the past object that continues to exist.  Hobbes, insofar as he treated our sensations as producing motions that continue to reverberate in the brain after the time of their initial impression, took such a position.  However, Locke was explicit that memory cannot involve storing the echoes or traces of past ideas away in some filing cabinet of the mind, like so many pictures or documents, and then pulling them out again when needed.  Were we to accept that view, we would have to accept that ideas continue to exist when not perceived and Locke did not want to make that supposition.  Rather, he took memory to be a capacity to recreate ideas we have had before and that have since disappeared, even though the sensory stimulus that originally produced them is no longer present.

But then how do we distinguish these ideas from ideas currently being produced in us?  How do we know that we are remembering?  We cannot say that this is because there are no motions or impressions currently being communicated by our senses to our brains to cause the ideas, because all that we are ever aware of is our ideas, not the activities in the brain that are supposed to cause them.  Neither can we say that it is because we are aware of deliberately producing them.  While we do deliberately produce memories, this does not suffice to distinguish memory from imagination.  Given that we have no innate ideas, imagination is, like memory, confined to reproducing ideas we have had before, in sensation or reflection.  The only difference is that in memory we reproduce ideas in the same sequence we have had them in the past, whereas in imagination we are not bound to do this (though it is not impossible that we might by accident).  But since we are now attempting to account for memory, we cannot say that memory is an ability to reproduce ideas in the sequence they originally occurred in experience, because how would we know what that sequence was?  To presume that the order in which ideas are produced is guided by knowledge of the sequence in which they originally occurred is to presuppose the very thing we are trying to explain, a memory of the order in which the ideas originally occurred.  To suppose that we just have an ability to reproduce ideas we have had in the past without being guided by any left-over trace or impression of the original sequence is to admit that we are only capable of imagination and leave it a problem how we ever manage to remember.

To solve this problem Locke declared that when we create an idea in memory we form the further idea that this idea was sensed at some time before, and attach this idea of “beforeness” to the idea we are currently creating.

However, this position raises further problems.  To remember an idea, on this account, is to attach to a currently existing idea the further idea that it was had before.  But what could make us think such a thing, if the currently existing idea exists now, rather than earlier?  To answer that we remember that an idea just like it was had earlier (or “before”) is unacceptable, because Locke is here supposed to be explaining what memory is.  To say that to remember is to now have an idea that you remember was had more vividly in the past is not an explanation of what memory is because it employs the very notion we are trying to explain as part of the explanation. So it looks like Locke would have to say that we are simply innately so constituted that when we perform the operation of remembering we simultaneously produce an idea of beforeness, which we attach to what we remember.

One problem with this approach is that beforeness is something that comes in degrees.  How do we know how much before or how earlier to consider a remembered idea to be? What gives us the capacity to not merely reproduce the idea, but keep track of how much time has passed since we had it so that we can attach the appropriate amount of “beforeness” to it?  It is not clear how these questions could be answered without presupposing that we somehow remember how long it has been since we last had the idea, though how we remember anything is just what is supposed to be explained).

Another problem concerns how Locke would account for the origin of the idea of beforeness.  He could not take it to be a simple idea of sensation, like our idea of red, because the idea of beforeness is not simple.  It is the idea of a relation that obtains between two things, an earlier one and a later one.  For Locke, ideas of relations arise as a product of the operation of comparison.  We consider two ideas together and discover some relation to hold between them.  But in the case of the idea of beforeness the two ideas we would need to consider together are an earlier idea and a later idea.  These are the only ideas that are appropriate to give us an idea of beforeness.  But if one of the two ideas is earlier then at least it (if not also its later partner) no longer exists.  (Alternatively, if it does, its later partner does not exist, because what is future no more exists than what is past.)  But the whole problem is how we manage to grab hold of an idea that no longer exists and contemplate it in memory.  Once again, it looks like we would have to have solved this problem in order to account for the acquisition of the idea of beforeness.  The idea of beforeness cannot, therefore, be invoked without circularity in order to explain how we manage to remember.

The only way out of the circle would seem to be to accept that the idea is innate, but that is hardly an option that Locke would be happy to countenance.

 

Discerning and Comparing.  When we perceive, it is typically the case that many different simple ideas are perceived together.  Some of these simple ideas may follow one another in time; others may be disposed alongside one another in space, and yet others may be bundled together, as figure and colour are bundled together in a colour patch.  Discerning is an operation of the mind that works like a more acute perception.  When we discern we isolate the individual simple ideas that our perceptions contain and contemplate them separately from one another.

We may also compare various perceptions, or even various simple ideas with one another.  This operation leads us to form ideas of the respects in which the ideas we are comparing resemble or are different from one another.  Our ideas of relations arise in this way.  These are highly refined ideas that are not given in sensation, and are not parts or aggregates of ideas of sensation, but are quite new ideas, though new ideas that can only arise in us insofar as certain other ideas have first been given in sensation and reflection and then compared in the right way.  It is through discerning and comparing that we come up with the idea of identity — the relation of being the same as — as well as the idea of difference — the relation of being different from.  The supposedly innate principles of the identity of indiscernibles (if there is no discernible difference whatsoever between one thing and another then they are the same), and the law of non-contradiction (nothing is the same as what is different from it) are read directly out of these relations.  But since the relations of identity and difference have to be learned by comparing and contrasting sensations, these principles cannot in fact be innate.

 

Repeating and Combining.  The mind also has the ability to imaginatively combine ideas that have originally been given separately from one another in distinct perceptions.  This is what accounts for all our fantastic ideas as well as for all our ideas of new inventions.  It is also what accounts for our mathematical and geometrical ideas of magnitudes in time and space and number, which are generated by taking a unit and adding it to itself.  Locke sometimes described combinations of multiple replicas of the same idea (like the idea of a unit repeated twice, three times, etc., to give us our idea of number) as “repeating.”  “Combining,” in contrast to repeating, involves combinations of different ideas.

 

Naming.  Naming is an operation whereby occurrences of a given idea are associated with a particular word.  A word is itself just a special kind of auditory or visual idea (a spoken word or written symbol).  Once we have named our ideas we can use these names to later call them to mind.

 

Abstracting.  Abstracting is the operation whereby the mind isolates some feature that a number of different ideas have in common and forms an idea just of that common feature.  (It is therefore importantly distinct from discerning and separating.) Abstraction gives rise to our generic ideas (i.e., our ideas of kinds of things or groups or classes, as opposed to our ideas of particular things).  All, or most of our words are in fact names of general ideas.  Very few are reserved to name particular objects.

 

ESSAY QUESTIONS AND RESEARCH PROJECTS

    1.     Critically assess Locke’s argument for inferring that our type (i) ideas must be resemblances of qualities in bodies.

    2.     Critically assess Locke’s arguments for inferring that our type (ii) ideas are not resemblances of any qualities actually inhering in bodies.

    3.     Locke’s claim that there is a distinction to be drawn between type (i) and type (ii) ideas was in part based on an appeal to the claim that type (ii) ideas are relative (the same water can feel warm to one hand but cold to the other) whereas our senses never give us conflicting information about the type (i) qualities of objects (no object ever feels like a globe to one hand but a cube to another    Essay II.viii.21). However, this claim seems obviously false in a number of cases (a pencil in a glass of water looks bent but feels straight, for example).  This is a point that was made by Bayle in note H of his Zeno article (to be read later in this class), by way of criticism of the Cartesian claim that a “blind impulse” leads us to think that material things are coloured, but a clear and distinct perception leads us to think that they must be extended.  However, it works just as well as a criticism of Locke, and both Berkeley (Principles 14-15) and Hume (Enquiry XII) used it as such.  Survey Bayle’s, Berkeley’s, and Hume’s statements of this objection and assess its adequacy.

    4.     Locke’s claim that there is a distinction to be drawn between type (i) and type (ii) ideas was also attacked by Berkeley (Principles 10, drawing on the argument of his Introduction to the Principles) on the grounds that it is impossible to form a type (i) idea without making use of a type (ii) idea.  This is because we cannot think of a figure without a boundary, and we cannot think of a boundary without employing contrasting qualities to mark its presence. Berkeley’s argument was later restated and improved upon by Hume (see his A treatise concerning human understanding, Book I, Part iv, Section 4).  Study Berkeley’s and Hume’s statements of this objection and determine whether Locke would have had any way of defending his position against it.

    5.     In his New essays on human understanding, Book II, Chapter 9, Section 8, Leibniz rejected Locke’s and Molyneux’s answer to the Molyneux question, writing that “the blind man whose sight is restored could distinguish [the cube and the sphere] by applying rational principles to the sensory knowledge he has already obtained by touch” (Remnant and Bennett, eds. [Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981], p.136).  Outline the reasons Leibniz gave for his view and the qualifications he applied to his positive answer.  Assess whether Leibniz or Molyneux has the stronger case.

    6.     It has occasionally been charged that Locke’s negative answer to the Molyneux question is inconsistent with his own position on the distinction between type (i) and type (ii) ideas.  According to this objection, if type (i) are resemblances of qualities in bodies, then the newly sighted person ought, on first seeing a globe or a cube, to be able to suppose that the type (i) ideas they receive from vision resemble qualities actually existing in bodies, and relate that information to their tangible experience in order to be able to say which object is the globe and which the cube. This objection is not supported by the interpretation of Locke’s reasons for agreeing with Molyneux that was offered in the reading notes.  However, the issue is not clear-cut.  Accounts of Locke’s position on the Molyneux question can be found both in works on Locke (e.g., E.J. Lowe, Locke on human understanding [London: Routledge, 1995], p.58, and in works on the history of psychology and of the theory of vision (e.g., Michael Morgan, Molyneux’s question [Cambridge, Cambridge University Press: 1977]).  Consult some of these works and determine whether Locke’s negative answer to the Molyneux Question is consistent or inconsistent with his position on the resemblance of type (i) ideas to features of bodies.

    7.     Locke was not the only early modern philosopher to have problems accounting for the phenomenon of memory.  Do a comparative and critical survey of attempts to account for the phenomenon of remembering by major and minor figures in the seventeenth and eighteenth century.  Particularly worthy of study are, in addition to Locke, Condillac, Hume, Immanuel Kant, and Thomas Reid.