What
is Property?
Much of the first
year of law school involves initiating students into the process of
learning to "think like a lawyer". Some might say that three years
is surely an excessive amount of time to accomplish this task, but
we hope that a brief introduction to some of the important concepts
in property law will demonstrate that the three years will be time
well spent.
The institution
of private property (which is only one method by which property can
be allocated), is generally thought of as "ownership" of "things",
as in "this is my bicycle". In legal terms, however, what is meant
by property is not the bicycle itself, but the legally enforceable
right of exclusive control over the bicycle. If I say, "this is my
bicycle", what this means is that you can't use my bicycle unless
I let you. I may decide to lend you my bicycle, or even sell it to
you if you offer me enough money, but in any case, the legal system
will protect my right of exclusive control. If you take my bicycle
without my permission, you will be punished as a criminal who has
committed theft. If you promise to buy my bicycle and then ride away
without paying me, the legal system will hold you to your word as
an enforceable promise, or a contract.
That property
is not about things, but about the relationships between those with
legal property rights and all others in relation to the subject matter
of the right, generally comes as a surprise to first year law students.
For many of these students, the words of C.B. Macpherson indicate
that critical thinking about everyday concepts is one of the most
important analytical skills involved in "thinking like a lawyer":
"Property
is not thought to be a right because it is an enforceable claim:
it is an enforceable claim because it is thought to be a human
right. The legal right must be grounded in a public belief that
it is morally right. Property always has to be justified by something
more basic; if it is not so justified, it does not long remain
an enforceable claim. If it is not justified, it does not remain
property."
-C.B. Macpherson
So now you know
two concepts from first year property law that are an important part
of the process of learning to "think like a lawyer": (1) property
is not about things, but the relationship between the holder of property
rights and all others; and (2) one of the most important rights of
private property is the right to exclude others.
|
|
The
Case for Private Property: Rationales and Justifications
The legal right
to property, as we have just learned, is premised on the societal
need to maintain relationships between people in the form of property
rights. The legal right is premised on a collective belief as to what
is morally desirable. In other words, property is not only a legal
relationship, but a political relationship as well, politics being
the process by which this social consensus is translated into enforceable
rights. Accordingly, a comprehensive understanding of property rights
requires an analysis of the various arguments advanced in support
of the institution of private property as perhaps the most common
method of holding property in the Anglo-Canadian legal system.
Economic
Arguments
Economists refer
to the concept of "efficiency" in terms of wealth maximization, understood
as the market condition in which it is not possible to improve any
one person’s position without a reduction in some other person’s welfare.
To achieve efficiency within the economic system, we must engage in
an optimal level of activity in any given pursuit, taking into account
the associated benefits and costs and arriving at a rational allocation
of resources accordingly.
A popular economic
rationale for private ownership is a parable known as "The Tragedy
of the Commons". Assume that several farmers are grazing their cattle
on a common pasture. Each farmer earns a given amount of profit from
the market value of each cow in his or her own herd, and so naturally
it will occur to each farmer that additional cows means additional
profit. The common pasture can only support a finite number of cows,
however, so in calculating the profit to be gained in increasing the
size of the herd, a farmer must take account of the costs in terms
of the reduction of available resources for grazing. The difficulty
with the nature of the pasture as a common resource is that while
an individual farmer receives the entire benefit of the market value
of each cow added to his or her own herd, the costs in terms of the
loss of available pasture consumed by each additional cow is distributed
among all of the farmers. Accordingly, it is to each farmer's advantage
to graze as many cattle as possible on this common pasture. Unfortunately,
given the finite amount of pasture land available, over-grazing is
the inevitable result, leading to the destruction of the pasture and
placing the farmers out of business.
Private ownership
is viewed as a solution to this tragedy as it forces each individual
farmer to assume, or "internalize", the full amount of both the benefits
and costs of adding additional cows to his or her own herd. Rather
than sharing the pasture as a common resource, each farmer is allocated
a given segment that is placed under his exclusive control. If he
or she introduces more cows than the allotment can bear, the result
is financial ruin for that particular farmer alone. Thus, each farmer
is motivated, or has the necessary "incentive", to manage his or her
resources effectively.

Economists do
acknowledge, however, that market failures can occur, leading to the
necessity of legal intervention. Returning to our game of Westernopoly,
recall that the Council flats were sitting empty. Can the Council
be said to be engaging in the optimal level of rental activity in
these circumstances? Has efficiency been achieved, or is it possible
to improve the allocation of vacant houses in a manner that benefits
both the Council and the people on the waiting list?
|
|
Labour
and Desert
This rationale
views labour as a predicate to private property. It suggests that
once labour is combined with a particular property interest, a right
in that object results. According to John Locke, a proponent and founder
of this theory, each one of us owns our own bodies or persons and
therefore our labour. When we work to produce a particular object,
by putting some of our ‘selves’ into it through our laborious effort,
we attain ownership rights in that particular object. We, in effect,
gain rights in the material world, which we create. Therefore, the
more one produces, or the more one labours to create, the more one
should also increase their own wealth, wealth being measured by rights
in property. This theory is founded on the premise that all persons
have a natural right and potential to attain rights in property.

Returning once
again to our game of Westernopoly, recall that we turned over a Chance
card stating that we made repairs upon moving into a vacant house
in the redevelopment area. Was this work sufficient to entitle us
to property rights in the vacant house?
Personhood
A contemporary
justification for the institution of private property is found in
the work of Professor Margaret Jane Radin, who first advanced a "personhood"
rationale whereby she claimed that a sense of ownership over a certain
amount of resources was essential to each person's moral development
and innate sense of humanity. Professor Radin has recently expanded
this theory to include what she describes as a form of "intuitive"
personhood. The value of private property is measured on a very personal
and unique level. For example, my favourite red baseball cap retails
for about $15, but the fact that it is my favourite cap, weathered
and worn in all the right places, makes it uniquely valuable. In the
same manner, a home provides more than shelter from the elements.
People value security and privacy, and the legal system protects these
values in the form of private property, whether we own or rent our
homes. A lack of private property of this nature, such as occurs in
situations of homelessness or unemployment, will result not only in
physical deprivation, but in significant emotional and psychological
distress as well. A person affected by these conditions will be unable
to engage in common social expressions of self-esteem.

Back to the game!
We had turned over a Chance card indicating that our relationship
was in trouble due to feelings of insecurity and low self-esteem.
Recall as well that the houses in the redevelopment area were worthless
to the Council, which considered them "not worthy of repair and not
fit to be occupied". To the players in our game, however, these "worthless"
houses allowed them to regain their sense of security and self-worth.
|
|
|
Enforcement
of Rights in Private Property: Substantive Law
Private property
is an enforceable legal right, its foundation evolving from a societal
need. In democratic societies, if society as a whole believes that
it is desirable to maintain relationships between people in the form
of property rights, then enforcement of those rights undoubtedly follows.
The state in turn implements substantive law, such as the law of trespass,
by which the legal owner of private property is able to exclude others
from gaining access.
What is trespass?
In Ontario, the
right to exclude others from private property is governed in part
by the Trespass to Property Act. Every violation of private
property, however minuscule, is a trespass. Unless you have the express
permission of the owner, you cannot enter private property, or engage
in any activity on private property, without being liable for trespass.
If you have committed a trespass, however, one method of avoiding
liability is to provide a justification or defence.
Can I avoid
liability by arguing the defence of necessity?
Circumstances
of urgent necessity, such as grave and imminent risk to life, may
sometimes (although not often) excuse conduct which would otherwise
be illegal or unlawful. The defence of necessity has generally not
been successful in criminal cases: see for example, R. v. Dudley and
Stephens (1884), 14 Q.B.D. 273, wherein the accused, two sailors adrift
at sea in a lifeboat and starving after 18 days, killed and ate the
cabin boy. However, the defence of necessity has been successful in
at least one case involving interference with private property rights:
see for example, Mouse's Case (1609), 12 Co. rep. 63), wherein
a casket belonging to Mouse was thrown overboard to lighten a barge
in danger of sinking during a storm. What appears to be significant
is the seriousness and imminence of the risk versus the gravity of
the illegal or unlawful conduct. If one can prove that it was of necessity
that they committed a trespass, then they will have successfully defended
the charge.
|